Towards a Pauline eros ethic
FRANCIS WATSON
Issues
of gender and sexuality have recently come to the fore in all humanities
disciplines, and this book reflects this broad interdisciplinary situation,
although its own standpoint is a theological one. In contrast to many
contemporary feminist theologies, gender and sexuality (eros) are here
understood within a distinctively Christian context characterized by the
reality of agape — the New Testament’s term for the comprehensive
divine-human love that includes the relationship of man and woman within its
scope. The central problem is addressed by way of key Pauline texts relating to
gender and sexuality (i
Corinthians ii, Romans 7,
Ephesians 5), texts whose influence on western theology and culture has been enduring
and pervasive. They are read here in conjunction with later theological and
non-theological texts that reflect that influence — ranging from Augustine and
Barth to Virginia Woolf, Freud and Irigaray. As in the author’s previous books,
the intention is to practise a less restrictive approach to biblical
interpretation which locates the texts within broad theological and
intellectual horizons.
Francis watson
is Professor of New Testament Exegesis at the University of Aberdeen. He took
his D.Phil. at Oxford and from 1984 to 1999 was Lecturer in New Testament
Studies and Reader in Biblical Theology at King’s College London. Professor
Watson’s previous books are Paul, Judaism and the Gentiles (1986), Text,
Church and World (1994), and Text and Truth (1997).
This Page Intentionally Left Blank
Towards a Pauline sexual ethic
FRANCIS WATSON
Disciplinary
boundaries within the theological curriculum are a necessary concession to the
complexity of the subject matter and the inevitable limitations of the
individual scholar. It makes good pragmatic sense that one person should be a
New Testament scholar, another a systematic theologian, and another an
ethicist ± so long as the boundaries remain open, ensuring freedom of movement
between the disciplines. But where boundaries are closed, they de®ne a subject
matter which is now held to be the exclusive preserve of a single group of
scholars. Communication between the disciplines is subject to severe
restrictions. Thus, the New Testament scholar becomes incapable of serious
theological reflection on the New Testament texts. The systematic theologian
makes only cursory forays into the fields of the biblical scholar or ethicist,
and may even believe that an apology is due for trespassing in someone else’s
professional domain. The ethicist may seek to develop a Christian ethical
reflection that shows scant regard for any theological or biblical foundations.
In this way, ‘theology’ becomes a flag of convenience for a number of related
but basically autonomous disciplines. All sense that Christian theology is
ultimately concerned with a single, simple subject matter disappears.
This book represents
my third attempt to develop an interdisciplinary approach to biblical interpretation
that refuses to be deterred by the warning notices that biblical scholars have
posted at regular intervals along the boundaries of their discipline: notices
that warn against allowing contemporary concerns to undermine the integrity of
pure scholarship, and that prohibit all serious theological engagement with the
biblical texts — on the grounds that such an engagement is inevitably partisan,
confessional and divisive. Insofar as they identify a number of possible
dangers, these warnings are certainly not groundless. But they should never
have been regarded as absolute laws, dehning the limits of the discipline and
closing it in on itself. They are at best no more than guidelines for
interdisciplinary dialogue, and they may or may not be relevant in any given
instance.
This particular
exercise in interdisciplinary dialogue takes the form of a study in Christian
sexual ethics which proceeds by way of a series of readings of three selected
Pauline texts. The intention is not to offer an exegesis of the Pauline texts
to which is appended, secondarily, some consideration of their ‘contemporary
relevance’. Ascertaining what the texts say is indeed a necessary hrst step,
and at this point standard exegetical methods are indispensable. But in the
last resort, to interpret is to use the texts to think with. To conhne
interpretation to the ever more precise reproduction or retracing of what the
texts say is to neglect their canonical function, which is to generate
thought, not to restrict it. Their genre as canonical texts demands that they
be set within broad horizons, and not merely returned to an ‘original
historical situation’ in the hrst century.
The Pauline texts
relating to sexuality and gender are few, brief and cryptic. They often fail to
say what we think they should say, and we sometimes wish they had left unsaid
what they actually do say. They are a problem for us. Yet they have been
extraordinarily inhuential. Along with the texts of Genesis 1—3 which they
themselves have mediated to subsequent Christian tradition, these Pauline
texts are deeply embedded in Christian ethical rehection, from Tertullian and
Augustine to Barth, and beyond. A rich heritage, a living tradition for us to
enter into? Or does the extent of these texts’ inhuence simply increase our
unease? If these texts do not say what they ought to say, and say what they
ought not to say, then their blindnesses and errors will be writ large across
the entire tradition they have helped to shape. In these circumstances, a
contemporary Christian sexual ethics might do better simply to abandon
Paul (after subjecting him to the necessary critique). A movement ‘towards
a Pauline sexual ethic’ is surely unthinkable? ‘Away from’, perhaps, or
(preferably) ‘beyond’, but not ‘towards’?
In this
book, I shall not be reading the selected Pauline texts uncritically. But my
readings are governed by the assumption that the appropriate criteria for
judging them are available to us only in and through the texts themselves, in
their testimony to the reality of the divine agape. If agape — the
inner-trinitarian love opened up to human participation in Jesus and his Spirit
— is the beginning and end of Christian faith and living, then it is agape that
must provide the final criteria for Christian reflection on sexuality and
gender. But this agape is not present to us in unmediated form, and can only be
articulated through engagement with the canonical texts. What these texts say
or do not say about sexuality and gender must be read in the light of their
unique and irreplaceable testimony to the divine agape that has taken the form
of a corresponding human agape, in Jesus and, through his Spirit, in a
community in which there are both men and women, together and not apart from
one another. These men and women are no strangers to the reality of eros. But
they practise together a qualitatively different love, whose origin and pattern
is the divine love to which they are constantly redirected, in worship,
preaching and sacrament, and in their mutual presence to one another. ‘We love,
because he first loved us’ (1 Jn. 4.19): whatever is said about sexuality and
gender must conform to that confession.
Yet
there must be engagement not only with the text but also with the world — the
‘secular’ world which, especially in recent times, has had much to say on the
topics of sexuality and gender that is directly relevant to the interpretation
of the canonical texts. In each of the three parts of this book, a
verse-by-verse theological interpretation of a selected Pauline text is therefore
preceded by a reading of a modern text that deals with closely related issues
in the conceptuality and idiom of our own times. Although ostensibly ‘secular’
in orientation, these modern texts belong — consciously or unconsciously —
within the Wirkungs- geschichte of the Pauline texts with which they are
here linked. Texts by Woolf, Freud and Irigaray will naturally not say the same
thing as the Pauline texts with which they are paired (1 Cor. 11, Rom. 7 and
Eph. 5). But not saying the same thing is simply a precondition of fruitful
dialogue. Readings of these modern texts open up interpretative possibilities
that would never have come to light if we con®ned ourselves to the safety of
the canonical text, refusing the risk of engagement with the secular. A further
dimension is added when the Pauline texts are read in conjunction with the
readings of Christian interpreters such as Augustine and Barth. Throughout,
the intention is to articulate the distinctive logic (or theo-logic) of a Christian
sexual ethics that necessarily takes the form of a biblical sexual
ethics — if the term ‘biblical’ can be freed from its biblicistic connotations.
I am deeply indebted
to Michael Banner, Richard Hays and Douglas Campbell, for many insights into
(respectively) theological ethics, New Testament ethics and Pauline
interpretation. Although — the conventional disclaimer — they are not to be
held responsible for the views I here develop, I do not think that this book
would have been written without them. I am also grateful to Grace Jantzen, Emma
Tristram and Nicholas Watson, who read the ®rst chapter in draft and helped me
to clarify my thinking about the book as a whole.
PART I
Velamen: 1 Corinthians 11
Whatever
the later and earlier material that must also be taken into account, and in
spite of the difficulties, the aim here is a ‘Pauline sexual ethic’ — an ethic
grounded in the Pauline texts and already partially embodied in the ongoing
life of the Christian community, yet requiring to be articulated anew in a situation
in which it is exposed to previously unheard-of pressures and challenges. The
‘ethic’ that is to be articulated does not consist primarily in a set of
prescriptions for sexual conduct. Not that it omits to prescribe, or consigns
the whole area to individual freedom of choice so long as this is exercised in
a manner respectful of the freedom of the other. It does prescribe — yet not in
a vacuum, but out of an ethos which provides the underlying rationale for its
prescriptions and makes persuasive and compelling what might otherwise seem
arbitrary and repressive.
This Pauline ethos
is that of a community in which men and women together participate in the grace
of the Lord Jesus Christ, the love of God, and the common life (koinonia)
of the Holy Spirit. Here, the love of God is poured into our hearts by the Holy
Spirit given to us — a divine love that issues in a responsive human love
towards God and the neighbour. It is on the basis of this ethos of love that it
can be said that woman is not apart from man nor man from woman, in the Lord
and within the Christian community. Here, the agape that binds women and men
together is not that of eros. Unless eros is assigned to its proper limits, it
is the corruption of love and not its fulfilment. The admittedly ambivalent
symbol of the veil or head-covering is to be understood in this light, as a
barrier intended to ward off the male erotic look that would prevent woman’s
voice from being heard, as, in prophecy and prayer, she utters the word of God
to the congregation and the responsive word of the congregation to God (1 Cor.
11). Far from being a sign of her subordination, the veil is her authority to
speak in this way. Since this divine-human dialogue is the articulation of
agape, it can also be said that the veil signihes the necessary distinction
between eros and agape, excluding the one so as to preserve the space of the
other.
Yet the veil remains
an ambivalent symbol. It makes woman invisible, and can all too easily be seen
as the hrst step towards the silencing of women that occurs a few chapters
later, at least in the hnal form of the Pauline text. The veil can also be seen
as signifying not the exclusion of eros for the sake of agape but the exclusion
of women for the sake of an all-male church leadership. Statements
subordinating women to male ‘headship’ are, after all, found in this very
passage, which can indeed be read as a series of proof-texts demonstrating the
need for a ‘postChristian feminism’ that separates itself from what it
perceives as an irredeemably patriarchal church. Because this reading must be
taken seriously, both as a reading of the text and as a reading of church and
society in and through the text, we preface a reading of the Pauline text in
terms of the problematic of agape, eros and gender (chapter 2) with a reading
of a modern text that is itself — in part — a critical feminist reading of the
Pauline text: Virginia Woolf’s Three Guineas (chapter 1). Its author
advocated a ‘separatist’ feminism according to which women must learn to
embrace and exploit the role of‘Outsider’ that has been assigned to them; she
lacked any formal theological training, and had no intention of arguing
theologically. Yet, despite her manifest intentions, her text can still be read
as a critical afhrmation — and on Christian theological grounds — of the
Pauline claim that man and woman belong together.
CHAPTER
ONE
‘Neither
is woman apart from man nor man apart from woman, in the Lord’ (i Cor. ii.ii). In the Lord, woman and man are
not independent of one another but interdependent. They face each other and
must constantly reckon with the being of the other. They do not face away from
one another; they do not find their true being by taking a path that diverges
from the path of the other, crossing it only occasionally and accidentally. In
the Lord, they belong together. That is so within the Christian community, in
which Jesus is acknowledged as Lord, and also outside it; for, whether or not
Jesus is acknowledged, it remains the case that God ‘has put all things [panta]
in subjection under him’ (i Cor. 15.27). The sphere in which man and woman
belong together is coextensive with the sphere of this universal lordship. This
‘belonging-together’, to which all humans are called, is not a mere neutral
coexistence. It is the belonging-together of agape, a pattern of living with
others that this same Pauline text will later articulate and celebrate (1 Cor.
13).
Belonging-together
does not exclude difference. If difference were dissolved into homogeneity, it
would no longer be ‘man’ and ‘woman’ who belonged together; they would belong
together not as man and woman but only as sharing in an undifferentiated
humanity. In the Lord, humanity is not undifferentiated. But neither is the
difference an absolute heterogeneity, which would make it hard to speak of a
‘humanity’ in which woman and man both share. Belonging- together acknowledges
difference, but this is the difference of those who belong together, not the
difference of those who are separated. The possibility of separation — ‘woman
apart from man’, ‘man apart from woman’ — is raised only in the form of its
negation. Possibilities are not negated at random, however, and the negation
concedes that a self-definition that excludes the other might at least be
attempted. Man might define himself as apart from woman; woman might define
herself as apart from man.
What it
means for man to define himself apart from woman is clear enough. Speaking only
of himself, he either fails to notice her existence or construes it as the
mirror-image of his own. His identity is supposed to represent a universal
human norm. Her identity is submerged in his; it is taken for granted that what
is true of him must also be true, although secondarily and to a lesser extent,
of her. Man defines himself ‘apart from woman’ in the sense that the difference
represented by ‘woman’ is subsumed into a universal male identity. This selfdefinition
is inscribed within language itself: ‘man’ both included woman and suppressed
her difference by assimilating it to a male norm. As the universally human,
‘man’ is apart from woman. Within this schema of solitary universality, woman’s
difference may indeed be acknowledged as a subordinate reality — but only in
order that the distinctive male self-image might be reflected back in the
mirror of the other. In the mirror, the disclosure of the image is achieved
only by way of a reversal, in which right is seen to be right only in the image
that displays it as left, as its opposite. The image of the other may be
subject to praise or blame, but in either case the appearance of otherness is
an illusion: for the image of the other serves the image of the narcissistic
self and has no identity of its own outside that necessary service. Even in
speaking of woman as the image of the other, man continues to speak of himself.
It is
this project of male self-de®nition apart from woman to which the term
‘patriarchy’ polemically refers. Can this term do justice to the total
reality of the male—female relationship, throughout history? ‘Patriarchy’ might
represent a metanarrative, adapted perhaps from the claim of Marx and
Engels that ‘the history of all hitherto existing society is the history of
class struggles’.1 But it might also represent a model: a
framework within which to view reality, disclosing a truth that is neither the
truth of the whole nor a mere effect of the model itself; not the whole truth,
but truth nevertheless. Understood as a model, ‘patriarchy’ would not occlude
or compete with concepts such as ‘class’ and ‘race’ as means of articulating
the reality of human sociopolitical life in its irreducible complexity. Within
its limitations, ‘patriarchy’ identihes a project of male self-dehni- tion,
‘apart from woman’, whose effects are all too real. The critical use of this
concept in historical or theological analysis is itself always subject to
critical evaluation; the concept can never guarantee in advance the truth of
the analysis. Conversely, the possible dehciencies of the analysis need not
detract from the value of the concept.[i] [ii]
In reaction against
masculine self-dehnitions ‘apart from woman’, woman may dehne herself as ‘apart
from man’; and this project of resistance may present certain formal resemblances
to the masculine self-dehnitions it strives to counter. Thus, the male may now
serve as the image of the other in which the self-image — now the self-image of
woman — is disclosed. But the formal symmetry — man dehnes himself apart from
woman, woman dehnes herself apart from man — should not be allowed to mask the
underlying asymmetry. The two projects of self-dehnition cannot be seen as twin
expressions of a perennial, perhaps not very serious conflict of two equal and
opposite principles. In one project, self-assertion is the dominant element;
in the other, the resistance of the victim of that self-assertion. The
asymmetry of thesis and antithesis means that no cheap and easy synthesis is
available. Belonging-together does not represent a via media between
two equal and opposite extremes, ‘patriarchy’ and ‘feminism’. The two terms are
incommensurable — not only because of their historical asymmetry but also
because of the semantic indeterminacy of ‘feminism’. If the term ‘patriarchy’
refers to the project of male self-dehnition apart from woman, it is not clear
that ‘feminism’ refers univocally to the project of female self-dehnition apart
from man. ‘Feminism’ is a contested term; there are many feminisms, overlapping
and diverging. ‘Feminist’ rehection on the belonging-together of woman and man
is quite conceivable. The concept of belonging-together opposes not ‘feminism’
but those strands of feminism and feminist theology which either advocate or
(more likely) simply presuppose a self-dehnition apart from man.
The Pauline text
that speaks of the belonging-together of man and woman also speaks,
problematically, of the veiling or covering of woman’s head. The image of the
veil is taken up by one of the text’s woman readers, Virginia Woolf, in the
course of a polemical plea for woman’s separate identity.[iii] Her own text is not simply a reading of the
Pauline text; it is an account of the relation of man and woman that resists
compromise and premature synthesis, and that pushes the project of self-dehni-
tion apart from man in the direction of a separatist account of woman as
Outsider. Woman is dehned as Outsider in relation to the patriarchal
institutions that administer society and that lead it inexorably towards war.
She is Outsider in relation to patriarchal institutions in general, but more
particularly in relation to the Church, whose all-male priesthood represents
patriarchy’s innermost shrine and secret. The enor mity of this situation, so
cunningly concealed and so hard to grasp, makes it impossible for the Outsider
to co-operate with men even in the cause of justice and peace of which she
approves. Man has de®ned himself apart from woman, and the catastrophic social
consequences of his decision continue to hem us in. In de®ning herself apart
from man, woman is ®ghting for life itself, and the notion of an ultimate
belonging-together of man and woman is no more than a faint utopian glow on the
horizon.
This text is an
expression of what is now called a ‘postChristian feminism’, in which
separation from the Christian church is paradigmatic of separation from
patriarchal institutions in general. What is to be gained by engaging it in a
close reading? What will come to light is the extent to which Christian agape
as the basis of the belonging-together of man and woman is acknowledged in
this text itself, despite its manifest intentions. To bring this situation
to light is to expose the gulf between the transcendental basis of the
Christian community and its empirical reality; but it is also to detect
symptoms of the transcendental basis within empirical reality. Only through the
appearance of truth can idols and ideologies be exposed. If feminist critique
claims to be grounded in truth, it is at least conceivable that this
truth-claim is in the end positively related to the transcendental truth-claim
that a post-Christian, secularizing culture has sought to repress. That there
is this positive relationship has yet to be shown; to assume it a priori
would be theological wishful thinking. But if this relationship does not exist,
the nature and basis of the truth on which a feminist ideology-critique might
take its stand remains an open question; or rather, within the relativizing
ethos of postmodernity, an ineffable mystery.[iv]
THROUGH THE SHADOW OF THE VEIL
As she
prepared to write the work eventually published as Three Guineas (1938),
Virginia Woolf wrote in her diary for Tuesday 16 February 1932: 'I'm quivering
& itching to write my ± whats it to be called? ± ''Men are like that?” ± no
thats too patently feminist: the sequel then, for which I have collected enough
powder to blow up St Pauls' (Diaries, iv.77).[v] As the preceding lines show, her impatience has
been exacerbated by the petty annoyances of the day: there are problems with
Nelly and Lottie (the servants), Miss McAfee has turned down an article, and dinner
tonight with Ethel Sands means that much valuable time will be lost. But it is
characteristic of the intellectual to be able to draw a clear dividing-line
between ephemeral matters and the long-term project ± in this case, a writing
that will blow up St Paul's.
Why does
she want to blow up St Paul's? This building is identihed in Three Guineas
as one of a number of central London landmarks that together symbolize the
dominant masculine order ± along with the Bank of England, the Mansion House,
the Law Courts, Westminster Abbey and the Houses of Parliament (133). But is
that a good enough reason for wanting to blow it up? St Paul's differs from the
other buildings in explicitly placing itself under the aegis of a male patron.
The same is true, however, of another domed building in central London. In Jacob's
Room (1922), it is noted that 'not so long ago the workmen had gilt the
hnal “y” in Lord Macaulay's name, and the names stretched in unbroken hle round
the dome of the British Museum' (143). One of the readers (for the reference is
to the British Library, within the Museum) is 'Miss Julia Hedge, the feminist',
who was waiting for her books to arrive: 'Her eye was caught by the final
letters in Lord Macaulay’s name. And she read them all round the dome — the
names of great men, which remind us — “Oh damn’’, said Julia Hedge, “why didn’t
they leave room for an Eliot or Bronte?’’’ (144—5). But Julia Hedge has no
intention of blowing up the British Museum. As the narrator of A Room of
One's Own (1929), Virginia Woolf herself visits the British Museum in order
to research her forthcoming paper on ‘Women and Fiction’. Entering through the
swing-doors, ‘one stood under the vast dome, as if one were a thought in the
huge bald forehead which is so splendidly encircled by a band of famous names’
(24). She has, as it were, strayed into a male brain, and the thoughts about
women that she finds there are all the thoughts of men. However, although
irritated by what she finds, and especially by Professor von X.’s monumental The
Mental, Moral, and Physical Inferiority of the Female Sex, she never
betrays any inclination to blow up the British Museum. Why, then, is St Paul’s
chosen instead as the target of her incendiarism?
In The
Years (1937), Martin Pargiter, on his way to visit his stockbroker, passes
St Paul’s, part of the stream of ‘little men in bowler hats and round coats’,
of ‘women carrying attache cases’, of vans, lorries, and buses: ‘Now and then
single hgures broke off from the rest and went up the steps into the church.
The doors of the Cathedral kept opening and shutting. Now and again a blast of
faint organ music was blown out into the air. The pigeons waddled; the sparrows
fluttered’ (183). Admiring the building from the outside, Martin suddenly
recognizes his cousin Sara, who has been attending the service. He invites her
to lunch in a nearby restaurant, where the following dialogue takes place:
‘I
didn’t know you went to services’, he said, looking at her prayerbook.
She did not answer. She kept looking round her,
watching the people come in and go out. She sipped her wine . . . They ate in
silence for a moment.
He wanted to make her talk.
And what, Sal,’ he said, touching the little book,
‘d’you make of it?’ She opened the prayer-book at random and began to read:
‘The father incomprehensible; the son
incomprehensible - ’ she spoke in her ordinary voice.
‘Hush!’ he stopped her. ‘Somebody’s listening’.
In deference to him she assumed the manner of a
lady lunching with a gentleman in a City restaurant. (185)
To
attend a service at St Paul’s is to behave abnormally. Individuals may break
off from the passing crowd to do so, but they thereby identify themselves
precisely as individuals, who may justly be interrogated about their conduct.
Sara’s answer is drawn from the Quicunque vult, which, as her
prayer-book would inform her, is ‘commonly called the Creed of Saint
Athanasius’ and is appointed to be sung or said at Morning Prayer on certain
feast days in preference to the Apostles’ Creed. The words of this text belong
only to the ecclesiastical interior of St Paul’s and are quite inappropriate on
the secular exterior. To utter these words, in a restaurant, where there are
many to overhear it, and in one’s ordinary voice, is to commit a solecism. Sara
is therefore silenced, even though Martin had previously ‘wanted to make her
talk’. More to the point, the words she quotes are no answer to the question
that has been put to her. They merely confirm the abnormality of the interior
and of those who worship there. What concern can Sara possibly have with the
incomprehensible father and the incomprehensible son to whom the worship is
addressed? A woman may reasonably enter the ‘huge bald forehead’ of the British
Library and become for a while a thought in a vast male brain; for, although
all the thoughts about women there are men’s thoughts, their progenitors are only
men. They are not God. The woman reader who has infiltrated the brain can sit
there drawing her caricature of Professor von X. with impunity. But what if she
enters the huge bald forehead of St Paul? (An ancient source assures us that St
Paul was indeed bald.)[vi] She can hardly sit there drawing caricatures of
the incomprehensible father and son; for they are not human, they are divine.
The all-male relationship that lies at the heart of the deity is underlined by
Sara’s mention only of the father incomprehensible and the son
incomprehensible, without proceeding with the Creed to the Holy Ghost
incomprehensible. Sara’s conduct in worshipping at St Paul’s is as incomprehensible
as the father and the son. It participates in their incomprehensibility, and
her response tacitly acknowledges this. Woolf’s narrator therefore remains
resolutely on the outside, along with Martin, approaching closely enough to
hear snatches of organ music and of the ‘faint ecclesiastical murmur’ from
within (184), but declining to 7 enter.[vii]
Here then is the
reason for the planned incendiarism: St Paul’s represents the deihcation of the
male. At the British Museum, the male is still recognizably human, and even the
names around the dome — Macaulay and the others — are at best only half-way to
deihcation. At St Paul’s, the situation is otherwise. St Paul himself is human,
but the father and the son whose names circulate in his brain are not. They are
divine, and they therefore appear to represent an exclusively masculine
symbolic order in which God is the male and the male is God. The unique
function of St Paul’s is therefore to project into transcendence the
male-dominated social order represented by the other great buildings of central
London. The material that will blow up St Paul’s will also bring down the whole
of that social order with it.[viii]
Incendiary imagery
is still employed in the hnal form of the text that Woolf envisages in 1932;
but it plays a subordinate role, as behts a pacihst manifesto, and it is not
now directed against St Paul’s cathedral. In Three Guineas the building
escapes attack, but the man whose name it commemorates does not. St Paul, we
learn here, ‘was of the virile or dominant type, so familiar at present in
Germany, for whose gratihcation a subject race or sex is essential’ (300). St
Paul is assimilated to Hitler.
Three Guineas is a substantial
work, comparable in scale to a medium-length novel and divided into three parts
that correspond to the ‘three guineas’ of the title. Its setting is fictional.
A male correspondent wrote, three years ago, asking Woolf or her fictional alter
ego how she thinks war can be prevented. Now at last she writes her reply.
Although she has long been deterred by the difficulty of the question, ‘one
does not like to leave so remarkable a letter as yours — a letter unique in the
history of human correspondence, since when before has an educated man asked a
woman how in her opinion war can be prevented? — unanswered’ (117). Embedded in
her response are replies to two further letters, one from the treasurer of a
women’s college, the other from the secretary of a society for promoting the
interests of professional women. After due reflection and with considerable
ambivalence, a cheque is sent to each (parts 1 and 2), and to the initial
correspondent, who is the secretary of a society devoted to the prevention of
war (part 3). In the end, however, the emphasis falls on the need for women to
resist assimilation to male institutions — the academy, the professions, even
the anti-war society whose paci®st convictions Woolf shares. Declining the
invitation to join, Woolf announces the formation of an unstructured ‘Society
of Outsiders’, in which women dedicate themselves to analysis and critique of
the patriarchal order.
The Pauline
injunction that women should be veiled serves initially as an image of women’s
unjust, oppressive con®nement to the private sphere. At this point, St Paul
incarnates the ®gure of the dictator. He is Creon, who shut Antigone up in a
rocky tomb; he is Hitler, and the obscure authors of letters to the newspapers
demanding that women be banished from the workplace. In the passage on veiling,
Paul invokes ‘the familiar but always suspect trinity of accomplices, Angels,
nature and law, to support his personal opinion’, arriving a few chapters later
at ‘the conclusion that has been looming unmistakably ahead of us’ — that women
are to be silent outside the con®nes of their own homes (299). St Paul presided
grimly over the whole Victorian concept of 'chastity', which affected every
aspect of female behaviour; and 'even today it is probable that a woman has to
fight a psychological battle of some severity with the ghost of St Paul' (301).
The way forward, it seems, is to do away with the Pauline veil which —
ever-present although almost invisible — divided the private sphere of women
from the public sphere of men. The veil must be consigned to the past; only
reactionaries want to reimpose it.
And yet the marginal
position represented by the veil is also a prerequisite for the critique
of the patriarchal order undertaken by the 'Society of Outsiders', in word and
deed. The veil — or the shadow still cast by this now-outmoded garment — gives women
a curious and critical perspective on the professional world of men. This
masculine world must be seen 'through the shadow of the veil that St Paul still
lays before our eyes', and from this angle it is undoubtedly a strange place:
At
first sight it is enormously impressive. Within quite a small space are crowded
together St Paul's, the Bank of England, the Mansion House, the massive if
funereal battlements of the Law Courts; and on the other side, Westminster
Abbey and the Houses of Parliament. There, we say to ourselves . . . our
fathers and brothers have spent their lives. All these hundreds of years they
have been mounting those steps, passing in and out of those doors, ascending
those pulpits, preaching, money-making, administering justice. It is from this
world that the private house . . . has derived its creeds, its laws, its
clothes and carpets, its beef and mutton. (133)
But as
women look more closely, they are astonished at what they ®nd. Who would have
thought that men took such pleasure in dressing up?
Now
you dress in violet; a jewelled crucifix swings on your breast; now your
shoulders are covered with lace; now furred with ermine; now slung with many
linked chains set with precious stones. Now you wear wigs on your heads; rows
of graduated curls descend to your necks. Now your hats are boat-shaped, or
cocked; now they are made of brass and scuttle shaped; now plumes of red, now
of blue hair surmount them . . . Ribbons of all colours — blue, purple, crimson
— cross from shoulder to shoulder. After the comparative simplicity of your
dress at home, the splendour of your public attire is dazzling. (134) This
clothing not only looks striking, it also speaks. Every item has symbolic
meaning, and every detail serves to communicate the wearer's status,
achievements, and moral and intellectual worth. This comprehensive professional
dress code is illustrated by a series of photographs of‘a general’, ‘heralds’,
‘a university procession’, ‘a judge’ and ‘an archbishop’, which serve to
locate the text as a piece of anthropological research into an exotic tribe
whose offices and institutions will be quite unfamiliar to readers.
Yet, seen from the
perspective of the Outsider, ‘through the shadow of the veil’, this dress code
is sinister as well as exotic. Within it there lurks a culture of war.
The connection is obvious: ‘Your ®nest clothes are those you wear as soldiers’
(138). The professional dress code is a seamless garment, and at its centre
lies the seductiveness of military uniform — which, even now, clothes the
reality of immanent war in the false colours of an essentially masculine
patriotic fervour. In rejecting the dress code and its attendant honours,
Outsiders can make a small but de®nite contribution to the cause of peace. They
will maintain an attitude of complete indifference to their brothers’ fevered
preparations for war, refusing to participate in the accompanying rhetoric.
They will purge themselves of the destructive illusions of patriotism. The
Society of Outsiders would work in parallel with other societies dedicated to
the prevention of war, but it would hold itself aloof in order not to lose the
distinctive perspective of women. Women alone can observe the world from the
perspective of ‘the shadow of the veil that St Paul still lays upon our eyes’ —
a perspective which discloses that the ultimate truth underlying the male
world’s dazzling appearance is the culture of violence and war. A woman may be
intimidated in the workplace, a country may be annexed with bombs and poison
gas — and the same forces are at work in both cases. The veil, still signifying
separation, although this time within the public sphere itself, has now become
the necessary condition for perceiving the truth and for venturing whatever
acts of smallscale resistance are appropriate and possible. The veil is
women’s prerogative. Only women can belong to the Society of Outsiders; only
women look at the world ‘through the shadow of the veil’.
The feminism of this
text is shaped by a particular historical situation, marked by the movement for
women's emancipation on the one hand and the rise of Fascism on the other; and
its construal of this situation is limited by the perspective of one for whom
political power is held by ‘fathers and brothers' — that is, by close relatives
with whom she has much in common. ‘When we meet in the flesh we speak with the
same accent; use knives and forks in the same way; expect maids to cook dinner
and wash up after dinner; and can talk during dinner without much difficulty
about politics and people; war and peace; barbarism and civilisation . . .'
(118). Throughout the book, Woolf's concern is with ‘the daughters of educated
men', that is, with professional women, the hardships they have endured in the
recent past and the dilemmas they continue to face in the present. Nothing is
said of the hardships and dilemmas of those women who are expected to cook and
to wash up. Yet Woolf is conscious that she is speaking from the limited
perspective of a particular class, and makes no pretence to universality. In
this respect, she is perhaps more self-aware and self-critical than some more
recent feminisms, in which ‘women's experience' is understood as a
trans-cultural universal. In addition, in her overriding preoccupation with the
problem of war she addresses an issue that impinges on all social classes
alike.
More important than
the limitations of her feminist perspective is her vacillation between the
feminist projects of ‘equal rights' and ‘separate identity', with a constant
bias towards the latter.9 This vacillation is dramatized in the ambivalent
symbol of the veil, drawn from 1 Corinthians 11.2 — 16 as traditionally
understood. The veil signi®es the division of the public sphere inhabited by
men from the private sphere inhabited by women. As such, the veil is rejected,
and its instigator is denounced as
9 Alex Zwerdling gives an illuminating
account of the historical background to this tension between feminisms of
equality and of difference (Virginia Woolf and the Real World, Berkeley,
Los Angeles, London: University of California Press, 1986, 210—42). Woolf's
'separatist thinking was a radical departure from the assumptions of the
women's movement' (237), and was occasioned by her sense that 'the movement had
not suf®ciently divorced itself from the world created by men; it had been
largely uncritical of the existing institutions of society and anxious merely
to enter them' (238). The Suffrage movement's enthusiastic support for the
First World War exempli®es this lack of critical distance. the
archetypal male oppressor. The entire nineteenth- and twentieth-century
movement for women’s emancipation — and especially for admission to higher
education and to the professions — is presented as a struggle against the veil
and everything it represents. Despite real progress, the struggle continues;
the voice of the oppressor, demanding that women leave the workplace to men
and return to the home that is their natural habitat, is as loud in democratic
England as it is in fascist Germany. On the other hand, the danger is that
precisely as women succeed within the male world of the professions, they will
assimilate its culture — which is a culture of war. The possibility of a voice
of independent critique and resistance will have been eliminated. Women, existing
at the margins of higher education and the professions, should not resent their
marginality; they should treasure it. They must continue to stand within the
shadow of the dividing veil, identifying themselves as Outsiders who can
criticize the war-oriented world of the patriarchal institutions from a
privileged perspective. The veil of difference is to be rejected, but it is
simultaneously to be preserved. Having rejected it, women must now ensure that
the priceless treasure it offers — the Outsider’s privilege of critical insight
— is not lost. As the Outsider watches ‘the procession of educated men’, moving
onwards ‘like a caravanserie crossing a desert’ (183), it is vitally important
to ask the critical question: ‘Where is it leading us?’ (184).
The text dramatizes
the dilemma posed by different feminisms — one a feminism of equal
opportunity, the other a feminism of separation; one optimistic about the
possibility of reforming male-dominated institutions as women gain access to
them, the other pessimistic about this possibility and about the value of this
access. The claim that ‘woman is not apart from man nor man from woman, in the
Lord’, contained in a Pauline passage that Woolf discusses at some length, is
ostensibly rejected in favour of a feminism in which woman must dehne herself
as apart from man. Her ‘Outsiders’ are vehemently opposed to the church as the
archetypal patriarchal institution, and the idea that men and women relate
appropriately to one another ‘in the Lord’, in the ecclesial context of agape,
would have been instantly dismissed had Woolf bothered to mention it at all.
And yet, contrary to its author’s intentions, it is precisely this idea that
this ‘separatist’ text permits and encourages us to think. Woolf’s own text
shows that this initial ‘apart from man’ is actually the precondition for a
situation in which ‘neither is woman apart from man nor man apart from woman,
in the Lord’. Despite itself, her text gives grounds for the theological
conclusion that, in the Lord, women and men are interdependent.
THE THREAT OF PEACE
In Three
Guineas, Woolf sets her discussion of women’s place in a male-dominated
society in the context of the issue of war and peace. However widely the
argument ranges, the correspondent’s initial question — how can we prevent
war? — is never forgotten.[ix] The author and her correspondent are agreed that
war is an unmitigated evil and that it cannot be justihed. They maintain their
pacihst conviction even in the face of Fascism, at a historical juncture — 1938
— when the tide of public opinion is turning decisively against them. They do
not advocate a policy of‘appeasement’ that involves turning a blind eye to the
evils of Fascism. They agree that the essence of Fascism is its violence, and
that to oppose it with violence is to allow oneself to be corrupted by it.
Satan cannot be cast out by Satan. If the essence of Fascism is disclosed in
the violence that destroys Guernica or Coventry, what is it that is disclosed
when the target is Cologne or Dresden? The ‘horror and disgust’ evoked by
images of war are shared. ‘War, you say, is an abomination; a barbarity; war
must be stopped at whatever cost. And we echo your words. War is an
abomination; a barbarity; war must be stopped’ (125).
The author’s
correspondent is a man — a barrister, very much part of the masculine order
that the outsiders observe from their peculiar vantage point ‘through the
shadow of the veil’. Yet — to the author’s astonishment — he has broken ranks
by asking her advice about what might seem a purely masculine concern: war and
the prevention of war. He has also asked her for a donation for the pacihst
society of which he is honorary treasurer, thereby acknowledging the new
economic autonomy which (for the author) is a necessary condition for the independence
of mind presupposed by his question. On the basis of this apparently rather
hopeful situation, the author enthusiastically sends the anti-war society her
guinea — ‘would that it were a million!’ (226). And yet, asked to join that
society, she declines; for her rejection of war, ostensibly shared with her
correspondent, is located within a larger argument whose premises he may be
expected to reject. The problem of war is consistently interpreted as a gendered
problem. War is a male activity:
For
though many instincts are held more or less in common by both sexes, to fight
has always been the man’s habit, not the woman’s. Law and practice have
developed that difference, whether innate or accidental. Scarcely a human being
in the course of history has fallen to a woman’s rifle; the vast majority of
birds and beasts have been killed by you, not by us . . . (120—1)
Interpreted
in this light, the problem of war cannot be isolated from the wider problem of
men’s treatment of women. The same male violence of which war is the supreme
epiphany is also manifested in the fathers’ continuing attempts to subjugate
their daughters, locking them up in the private world of the home, or, if this
proves impossible, ensuring that their participation in the public world of
the professions remains as marginal as possible.
It is Fascism that
discloses the connection. Fascism glorihes the male warrior and the wife and
mother who heals his wounds and bears his children. It requires the separation
of the two worlds of men and women, the reversal of women’s hard- won freedoms,
and it can call upon a long legacy of hostility to those freedoms: the
hostility of men who feel threatened by them, and the hostility of women who,
lacking economic or intellectual independence from their husbands, have internalized
the patriarchal delimitation of their role. Far from being a pathological
phenomenon of certain societies remote from our own, Fascism actually discloses
the dynamics of ‘normal’ social life in capitalist countries that pride
themselves on their democratic traditions and their capacity for social
progress. There is no perceptible difference between English and German expressions
of the view that paid work is a male prerogative and that ‘homes are the real
places of the women who are now compelling men to be idle’ (174):
Are
they not both saying the same thing? Are they not both the voices of Dictators,
whether they speak English or German, and are we not all agreed that the
dictator when we meet him abroad is a very dangerous as well as a very ugly
animal? And he is here among us, raising his ugly head, spitting his poison,
small still, curled up like a caterpillar on a leaf, but in the heart of
England. (175)
As in
Freud’s account of sexuality, the distinction between the aberrant and the
normal cannot be maintained. The aberration discloses and grounds the reality
of the normal, as the excluded term of a binary opposition revenges itself on
the privileged term by recurring at its very heart.
In disclosing the
connections between war, maleness and the subjugation of women, Fascism thus
serves as a mirror in which a supposedly democratic society can see, even if in
heightened and exaggerated form, its own lineaments. But it is the female
author who holds this mirror up and invites her male correspondent to look
into it. Will he accept that what he sees there is in any sense a true
reflection of the society to which he belongs? Or will he argue, as many of
Woolf’s first readers did, that women’s emancipation, however important and
desirable, must now be subordinated to the far more urgent and quite different
concerns that arise from the threat of Fascism? Will he claim that it is one
thing to confine women to the home, quite another to subject that same home and
its inhabitants to the terrors of aerial bombardment? Even if he appears to
endorse the claim that Fascism is a mirror in which we see our own reflection,
will he be capable of retaining this insight by placing the oppression of women
at the centre of his political vision and holding it there? If he fails to do
so (as is all too probable), will it not be because ± as a bene®ciary of the
dominant patriarchal order who takes its privileges for granted ± he regards
the cause of women as much less important than the cause that he himself
espouses? The optimism that welcomes the new reality of ‘men and women working
together for the same cause’ (227) is tempered by the pessimistic conclusion
that ± as one of the working titles for this text puts it ± ‘men are like
that’. Because even the honorary treasurer of the anti-war society has been
shaped by the same social forces that have issued in the hypermasculinity of
Fascism, he too must be kept at a certain distance even as the integrity of his
work is acknowledged and honoured. The Outsiders share an experience of being
outside that he lacks, and this experience is a necessary although not a suf®-
cient condition of the integrity of their political vision.11
But is
it necessarily the case that ‘men are like that’, incapable of grasping that
the issue of gender is of fundamental political signi®cance? Woolf’s own
text gives grounds for doubting it. The question hinges on the issue of experience.
Is the respective experience of those whom Woolf coyly calls ‘the sons and
daughters of educated men’ so radically different that the sons are
constitutionally incapable of understanding what the daughters are saying?
The
honorary secretary of the anti-war society is introduced in the following
terms:
You
. . . are a little grey on the temples; the hair is no longer thick on the top
of your head. You have reached the middle years of life not without effort, at
the Bar; but on the whole your journey has been prosperous. There is nothing
parched, mean or dissatisfied in your
11 Woolf’s aloofness towards the anti-war
society may be compared to Mary Daly’s criticism of organizations that ‘fix all
their attention upon some deformity within patriarchy ± for example,
racism, war, poverty ± rather than patriarchy itself, without recognizing
sexism as root and paradigm of the various forms of oppression they seek to
eradicate’ (Beyond God the Father: Towards a Philosophy of Women's
Liberation [1973], London: The Women’s Press Limited, 1986, 56). As Woolf
proposes a Society of Outsiders that will preserve women’s distinctive identity
and experience, so Daly advocates a 'sisterhood of women’, that is, of those
women who 'decide that independent ''bonding’’ with each other and cooperation
on this basis with male- governed groups is the better choice’ (59). Like
Woolf, Daly ®nds intimate connections between masculinity and war, and sees in
Fascism the full disclosure of a 'masculine metaphysical madness’ that is still
alive and well today (120). expression.
And without wishing to flatter you, your prosperity - wife, children, house —
has been deserved. You have never sunk into the contented apathy of middle
life, for, as your letter from an office in the heart of London shows, instead
of turning on your pillow and prodding your pigs, pruning your pear trees — you
have a few acres in Norfolk — you are writing letters, attending meetings,
presiding over this and that, asking questions, with the sound of the guns in
your ears. For the rest, you began your education at one of the great public
schools and finished it at the university. (117—18)
The
description appears to make the correspondent a typical representative of the
male-dominated establishment, marching confidently near the front of the
strangely attired procession of fathers and brothers, an unknowing participant
in the culture of violence that it secretly represents. The division between
the sexes seems at this point to be absolute: ‘Obviously there is for you
some glory, some necessity, some satisfaction in fighting which we have
never felt or enjoyed’ (121; italics added). But if that description ®tted the
correspondent, he would never have written asking how war could be prevented;
and he would never have become honorary treasurer of a society that holds that
‘war must be stopped at whatever cost’ (125). If he has written ‘with the sound
of guns in [his] ears’, that sound is presumably not music to his ears but an
unspeakable cacophony. But that means that he has seen through the illusions of
a particular masculine self-image, which Woolf illustrates from a biography of
a certain Viscount Knebworth: ‘The difficulty’ — his biographer writes — ‘to
which he could find no answer was that if permanent peace were ever achieved,
and armies and navies ceased to exist, there would be no outlet for the manly
qualities which ®ghting developed, and that human physique and human character
would deteriorate’ (122). Woolf acknowledges, however, that this ideology of
masculinity is by no means universal by quoting the testimony of the poet
Wilfred Owen:
Already
I have comprehended a light which will never filter into the dogma of any
national church: namely, that one of Christ’s essential commands was: Passivity
at any price! Suffer dishonour and disgrace, but never resort to arms. Be
bullied, be outraged, be killed; but do not kill . . . Thus you see how pure
Christianity will not fit in with pure patriotism. (122)
According
to Woolf, this is very much a minority view among men. The vast majority 'are
of opinion that Wilfred Owen was wrong; that it is better to kill than to be
killed' (123). Yet her correspondent remains, as late as 1938, a committed
advocate of the minority position. Middle-aged now, he belongs to the
generation of Wilfred Owen ± the generation that was decimated in the years
from 1914 to 1918. The sound of guns in his ears is the sound not only of the
next war but also of the last war; the gun®re sounds loudly and persistently in
his own memory. His paci®sm is almost certainly the result of a similar
revelation to the one described by Owen. As a member of the ruling classes, he
will have been a member of the 'national church' and assimilated the prevailing
ideology of manliness and military glory. Judging from his background, he is
unlikely to have been a conscientious objector. Like Owen, he will have learned
his pacihsm not second-hand but as the result of hrst- hand experience of
risking being killed, of killing, and of seeing others killed.
His pacihsm stems
from a hrst-hand experience of war that his sister lacks. According to Woolf,
'the daughters of educated men' responded with enthusiasm to the events of
August 1914 because military hospitals, helds and arms factories offered them
an alternative to the intolerable conhnement of the private house. 'Consciously
she desired ''our splendid Empire”; unconsciously she desired our splendid war'
(161). It is as a nurse that the correspondent's sister comes closest to the
reality of war. Her experience of the immediate impact of war on human bodies
is, of course, hrst-hand; but she still lacks her brother's experience of
risking being killed, of killing, and of seeing others killed. She is at
relatively little risk of being killed. She has never directed machine-gun or
bayonet against her fellow human beings. She has no direct experience of the
sudden deaths of others, since her concern is with those who die lingering
deaths or who may recover from their wounds. Since war has always been men's
work and alien to her, her pacihsm will not fundamentally jeopardize her
identity as a woman. Her brother's situation is different. As a convert to
pacihsm, he has experienced what Woolf calls an 'emancipation from the old
conception of virility’ (322); but, if he lives in a society where the old
conception is still the majority view, his identity as a man will be called into
question. He is the intended target of the distinction between ‘a nation of
pacihsts and a nation of men’ (322): as it happens, the words are Hitler’s, but
the correspondent will be familiar enough with this disjunction between
pacihsm and masculinity from his own hrst-hand experience. As a pacihst who
refuses to bear arms, he is not a ‘real man’. As an advocate of ‘passivity at
any price’, he involuntarily takes upon himself the symbolic identihcation of
passivity with femininity. He becomes ‘effeminate’. He also exposes himself to
the accusation of ‘cowardice’, which may be voiced by women as well as by other
men. Experience shows, according to Woolf, ‘that a man still feels it a
peculiar insult to be taunted with cowardice by a woman in much the same way
that a woman feels it a peculiar insult to be taunted with unchastity by a man’
(316). The male’s susceptibility to such taunts indicates ‘that courage and
pugnacity are still among the prime attributes of manliness’ (317); it is also
a sign that, for men and women alike, pacihsm is incompatible with sexual
prowess. War is a spectacle intended to evoke feminine admiration, and to
decline war is to forfeit the admiration. To the slurs of effeminacy, cowardice
and impotence we must add another: treachery, the betrayal of one’s native
land. It is ‘patriotism’ that leads men to go to war, in the conviction that —
in the words of the Lord Chief justice of England — our country is ‘a castle
that will be defended to the last’ (123). Within an ideology such as this, what
is to be said of the man who — supposedly on moral grounds — does nothing and
allows the castle to be overrun? What does a man like that deserve? The
stirring rhetoric of patriotism is of a piece with the glamour of military
uniform, whose ‘splendour is invented partly in order to impress the beholder
with the majesty of the military ofhce, partly in order through their vanity to
induce young men to become soldiers’ (138). Women, ‘who are forbidden to wear
such clothes ourselves, can express the opinion that the wearer is not to us a
pleasing or an impressive spectacle’ (138); women can refuse to participate in
the violent sexual game that uniform signihes. Men may do likewise. But if they
do so, what is signified by the rhetoric and the spectacle will be their own
castration.
The rhetoric and the
uniform change over the years; but, although aware that 1938 is not 1914, Woolf
is chiefly struck by the continuities.[x] Underlying the changes the same gendered dynamics
are at work, apparently untouched even by the widespread revulsion evoked by
‘the Great War’. In that case, however, a man’s decision to be a pacifist -
advocating passivity at any price, holding that war must be stopped at whatever
cost — still jeopardizes his masculinity. This results not only in a certain
social stigma but also in insight: the ‘light’ that Owen claims to have
‘comprehended’ entails a new awareness of the social construction of gender. By
the light of this disclosure, a masculinity that has previously seemed entirely
natural, a non- negotiable bestowal of nature herself, is seen to be no more
than a set of cultural assumptions which can and must be changed. Despite his
apparent impotence, the pacifist is a challenge to the gender stereotype, and
the stigma that he experiences is an indication of the threat that he poses.
Since stereotypical views of masculinity and femininity are always coordinated,
the paci®st’s insight will encompass not only masculine stereotypes but gender
stereotypes in general. Gender ideologies do not focus on a single sex alone.
They are concerned with the duality, and a quality or role assigned to one
will be co-ordinated with a complementary quality or role assigned to the
other. A modification at one point will have effects throughout the system as a
whole. If, through the light of revelation, a particular construal of
masculinity becomes visible as such and is rejected, this cannot but affect the
corresponding construals of femininity. Of all men, the paci®st should be
peculiarly open to the feminist’s insight into the relation between war, gender
and the subordination of women. He cannot be regarded as just another
representative of an undifferentiated patriarchy.
The ‘patriarchy’
against which the Society of Outsiders dehnes itself is, in fact, not the
seamless robe that it takes itself to be. It is full of holes. Its project is
to cover the whole of reality, so that reality itself will appear as
patriarchal. Yet, at point after point, the gaps and tears in the garment allow
a reality to show through that is other than patriarchy and contrary to it. It
is these gaps and tears that make the existence of a Society of Outsiders
possible in the hrst place, for otherwise the seamless robe would enfold all
men and women alike and no one would be in a position to see through it. Even
in the case of the church (for Woolf, the Church of England), the patriarchal
project encounters serious difficulties. If we ask, Is war right or wrong?, the
church gives us no clear answer:
The
bishops themselves are at loggerheads. The Bishop of London maintained that
‘the real danger to the peace of the world to-day were the pacifists. Bad as
war was, dishonour was far worse’. On the other hand, the Bishop of Birmingham
described himself as an ‘extreme pacifist ... I cannot see myself that war can
be regarded as consonant with the spirit of Christ’. So the Church itself gives
us divided counsel - in some circumstances it is right to fight; in no
circumstances is it right to fight. (124)
This
division among the bishops has come to light in the Daily Telegraph, 5
February 1937, and is said, with heavy irony, to be ‘distressing, baffling,
confusing’. But it might better be seen as a faint sign of hope. We must look
more closely at this division and what it signihes.
In the hgure of the
Bishop of London, the church fulhls its calling, bestowed on it by patriarchy
itself, to be patriarchy’s transcendental guarantor. ‘London’ is a ht symbol of
the male- dominated world of public life: for there (as we already know)
‘within quite a small space are crowded together St Paul’s, the Bank of
England, the Mansion House, the massive if funereal battlements of the Law
Courts; and on the other side, Westminster Abbey and the Houses of
Parliament’. There ‘our fathers and brothers have spent their lives’ (133). It
is entirely proper that the Bishop who presides over this world should speak
for it. He knows that war is ‘bad’. He has noticed that people get hurt by it.
But it is not as bad as all that; it is not so bad that it ‘must be stopped at
whatever cost’. War, in fact, is good as well as bad. (The Bishop may perhaps
have pointed out here that war develops manly qualities, and that human
physique and character would deteriorate without it. Or he may have demonstrated
that the proposed war meets the criteria for a ‘just war’ that are decreed by
tradition.) It is not war but ‘dishonour’ - loss of self-esteem - that must be
stopped at whatever cost. The Bishop does not pause to consider whether the
crucihed Christ shares his views on war and dishonour, for he speaks here not
in Christ’s name but on the much more impressive authority of patriarchy
itself. Having braced himself for war and reassured himself with the thought of
its relative goodness, he not only dissents from ‘the pacihsts’ but actually
sees in them ‘the real danger to the peace of the world’. The pacihsts are
wolves in sheep’s clothing, and are exposed as such by the sharp eyes of the
Bishop - conscious as ever of his solemn duty to protect the genuine sheep from
predators.
In spite of these
almost unanswerable arguments, the Bishop suffers the severe embarrassment of
being contradicted by a brother bishop in the very same issue of the Daily
Telegraph. Birmingham lacks the prestige of London. The Outsider would
probably not have conceded that ‘at hrst sight it is enormously impressive’
(133) if she had taken Birmingham rather than London as her symbol of the
public world. In London, St Paul’s and Westminster Abbey stand for the Church’s
presence at the heart of the nation’s life. ‘Birmingham, on the other hand, had
not much interest in the Church . . . Its temper was . . . predominantly
Nonconformist.’[xi] London establishes the norm, Birmingham represents
dissent from the norm; London is the inside, Birmingham the outside. The Bishop
of Birmingham is therefore an Outsider, and as such, unlike his counterpart
in London, he is not ashamed to ask whether war is ‘consonant with the spirit
of Christ’ and to answer in the negative. He sees through the posturing of his
brother, for whom it is ultimately Christ’s command and practice of nonresistance
that is ‘the real danger to the peace of the world’.14
In doing
so, he exposes an embarrassing hole in the patriarchal fabric. Patriarchy must
pay lip-service to Christ if it is to have the transcendental guarantee that it
covets. But Christ proves himself to be unreliable. He shows a marked tendency
to evade the role that patriarchy would thrust upon him. One hopes and expects
to see him in the procession of fathers and brothers, but he seems to be
absent. He is an Outsider. Through ‘the spirit of Christ’, he is at work still
to shape a mode of being in the world that is fundamentally at odds with the
metropolitan norm.15
Two men
(a Poet, a Bishop) trace back to a third (Christ) a disclosure that forces them
to rethink the very nature of ‘manhood’. But to rethink masculinity is not to
rethink maleness
14 An account of the bishop’s pacifism is
given in John Barnes, Ahead of his Age: Bishop Barnes of Birmingham,
London: Collins, 1979, 344—64. For the broader context, see Alan Wilkinson, Dissent
or Conform? War, Peace and the English Churches 1900—1945, London: SCM
Press, 1986.
15 With the possible exception of Mary
Daly, recent feminist theology does not appear to endorse Woolf’s option for
pacifism. Feminist theology has often sought convergence with Latin American
liberation theology, which does not deny that there can be a legitimate
violence of the victim directed against the violence of the oppressor (see, for
example, Sharon D. Welch’s Communities of Resistance and Solidarity: A
Feminist Theology of Liberation, Maryknoll: Orbis, 1985, 15—31, where the
convergence between feminist and liberation theologies makes the question of
the violence of the victim a non-issue). Ched Myers acutely analyses liberation
theologians’ unease with Jesus’ practice of nonviolence, arguing that 'the
ambivalent relationship between Marxist political hermeneutics and the cross
suggests that it has already been decided, on other grounds, that the strategy
of nonviolence does not represent genuinely revolutionary politics’ (Binding
the Strong Man: A Political Reading of Mark's Story of Jesus, Maryknoll:
Orbis, 1991, 471)- The nonviolence at the heart of Jesus’ gospel 'has been
betrayed not only by interpreters of the right but of the left as well. For in
identifying his movement as a necessarily subversive one, the fact remains that
he calls his followers to take up the cross, not the sword. The way of
nonviolence reckons with execution, not dreams of Maccabean heroism and revolutionary
conquest . . . It is a deliberate revolutionary strategy, embraced in the
conviction that only nonviolence can break the most primal structures of power
and domination in the world, and create the possibility for a new order to dawn
in the world’ (286). The theological issue here is trenchantly expressed by
John Howard Yoder: 'Theologians have long been asking how Jerusalem can relate
to Athens; here the claim is that Bethlehem has something to say about Rome —
or Masada’ (The Politics of Jesus, Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1972, 13). alone, in
isolation. To be man is not to be man alone but to be man together with woman,
just as to be woman is to be woman together with man. The recognition that
Christ forbids the violence that is the traditional prerogative of the male is
a sign of hope for men and women alike.
THE ARCHBISHOP AND THE MANX CAT
Woolf
provides a set of photographs to illustrate her image of the procession of
fathers and brothers. The photographs con®rm her claims about the fathers' and
brothers' peculiar dress sense, and several of them also demonstrate their
fondness for processing. One is entitled ‘A University Procession’; and
processions are also under way in the photographs entitled ‘A Judge’ and ‘An
Archbishop’. The title, ‘An Archbishop’, indicates that the author intends to
draw attention to the type and not to the individual office-holder, whose name
is not given. Like the other fathers and brothers, he is, by modern standards,
oddly dressed. His mitre, with its peaks at front and back and its dip in the
middle, flaunts its difference from all other known headwear. His stole is
broad and richly embroidered, and is made of such thick and heavy material that
will-power alone keeps him from sinking under its weight. His left hand grasps
a thick wooden staff, surmounted by an elaborate silver structure vaguely
reminiscent of ecclesiastical architecture and presumably representing the
Church, which would fall to the ground were he to relax his grip. Against the
dazzling white background of his cassock there hangs a silver and jewelled
crucifix, signifying perhaps the indissoluble union of faith and temporal
power. But most striking of all is not his attire but his face. It is the
lined, hollow-cheeked face of an old man whose eyes, nose, mouth and jaw are
resolutely and grimly set as if to defy any who would challenge his right to
rule. Behind him, the downturned eyes and folded hands of an altar-boy express
an almost feminine submissiveness.
In
Virginia Woolf’s Orlando: A Biography (1928), there is a curious scene
during which the hero changes sex. Orlando is a young aristocrat, elevated to a
high position at court by the favour of Queen Elizabeth I and dispatched by
King Charles II as ambassador to Constantinople. Returning home as a woman, she
becomes the con®dante of literary luminaries such as Dryden, Pope, Swift and
Addison, marries and ful®ls her own literary ambitions during the Victorian
period, and marks her arrival at the present day (11 October 1928) by paying a
visit to Marshall and Snelgrove's, the department store. At the turning-point
of the book, the ambassador falls into a trance, and his biographer ®nds
herself at a loss as to how to proceed. Should she heed the counsel of the
Ladies Purity, Chastity and Modesty, who advise her to conceal the truth about
what happened next? But events overtook her as she deliberated. Trumpet blasts
appealed for the truth to be uncovered, and the virgin sisters fled in
disarray. Orlando awoke:
He
stretched himself. He rose. He stood upright in complete nakedness before us,
and while the trumpets pealed Truth! Truth! Truth! we have no choice but to
confess — he was a woman . . . No human being, since the world began, has ever
looked more ravishing. His form combined in one the strength of a man with a
woman’s grace. As he stood there, the silver trumpets prolonged their note, as
if reluctant to leave the lovely sight which their blast had called forth; and
Chastity, Purity, and Modesty, inspired, no doubt, by Curiosity, peeped in at
the door and threw a garment like a towel at the naked form which,
unfortunately, fell short by several inches. Orlando looked himself up and down
in a long looking-glass, without any signs of discomposure, and went,
presumably, to his bath. (97)
This
biographical account of a magical sex-change may appear to be frivolous, but
the question it raises is not at all frivolous. The question is this: if it
could happen to an Ambassador, could it also happen (mutatis mutandis)
to an Archbishop?
Woolf values the
church chiefly as an image of patriarchy in its purest and most transcendental
form. The God of whom it speaks ‘is now very generally held to be a conception,
of patriarchal origin, valid only for certain races, at certain stages and
times’ (319).[xii] Although God is dead, however, the church retains
an exemplary significance. Like Fascism, it can be held up as a mirror to
society at large. In particular, its refusal to allow women to minister in the
sanctuary aptly symbolizes women’s marginalization in public life. Because the
ordination of women would undermine the symbolic function she has assigned to
the church, Woolf is as resolutely opposed to it as is the Archbishop himself.
Yet she is genuinely interested in the report prepared by the Archbishops’
Commission (1935), in response to the request of ‘daughters of educated men’ to
be admitted to the priesthood. She reports at some length the theological and
exegetical arguments to which, as the Commission concedes, the daughters of
educated men can legitimately appeal, and she also quotes its guarded
conclusion: ‘While the Commission as a whole would not give their positive
assent to the view that a woman is inherently incapable of receiving the grace
of Order . . . we believe that the general mind of the Church is still in
accord with the continuous tradition of a male priesthood’ (252). But Woolf
underplays the admission that it is only tradition that bars women from the
ordained ministry, despite the theological arguments in its favour. She does
not see that, in conceding the weakness of its own case and the strength of the
opposing one, the Commission is in effect casting doubt on the permanent
masculinity of the Archbishop himself. The Commission as a whole would not give
positive assent to the view that the Archbishop is inherently incapable of
becoming a woman, although it believes that this would create some dif®-
culties for the general mind of the Church.
Woolf
fails to exploit this point partly because she does not wish women to be
ordained and partly because she is more interested in the report’s
psychological account of male resis
is no Shakespeare, there is no Beethoven;
certainly and emphatically there is no God; we are the words; we are the music;
we are the thing itself’ (A Sketch of the Past’ [1939-40], in Moments of
Being, 72). This philosophy derives from the revelatory moment, as
experienced by Mrs Ramsay in To the Lighthouse', the moment when one
becomes aware that 'there is a coherence in things; something, she meant, is
immune from change, and shines out (she glanced at the window with its ripple
of reflected lights) in the face of the flowing, the fleeting, the spectral,
like a ruby . . . Of such moments, she thought, the thing is made that remains
for ever after. This would remain’ (114).
tance to
women’s ordination. In declining to admit women to the priesthood, it seemed
advisable to the Commission ‘to give psychological and not merely historical
reasons for their refusal’ (253). Professor Grensted of Oxford was therefore
commissioned ‘to summarize the relevant psychological and physiological
material’ (253), and, following the conventional disclaimers about the limits
of psychological knowledge and the controversial nature of psychological
theories, he offered an analysis of male resistance to women priests, as
expressed in the predominantly hostile evidence presented to the Commission.
This resistance, he argues, is the product of an ‘infantile fixation’ — an
unconscious fear of women grounded in repressed memories of infantile
sexuality. It is, to say the least, a novelty for a church report to appeal to
Freudian speculations about a ‘castration complex’, and to trace the general
mind of the church back to an ‘infantile fixation’. Grensted writes:
This
strength of feeling, conjoined with a wide variety of rational explanations, is
clear evidence of the presence of powerful and widespread subconscious
motives. In the absence of detailed analytical material . . . it nevertheless
remains clear that infantile ®xation plays a predominant part in determining
the strong emotion with which this whole subject is commonly approached . . .
Whatever be the exact value and interpretation of the material upon which
theories of the ‘oedipus complex’ and the ‘castration complex’ have been
founded, it is clear that the general acceptance of male dominance, and still
more of feminine inferiority, resting upon subconscious ideas of woman as ‘man
manque’, has its background in infantile conceptions of this type. These
commonly, and even usually, survive in the adult, despite their irrationality,
and betray their presence, below the level of conscious thought, by the
strength of the emotions to which they give rise. It is strongly in support of
this view that the admission of women to Holy Orders, and especially to the
ministry of the sanctuary, is so commonly regarded as something shameful. This
sense of shame cannot be regarded in any other light than as a non- rational
sex taboo. (254)
Underlying
this aetiology of resistance to women’s ministry is a Freudian tale that is
judiciously left untold, although it is hinted at. Hostile emotions well up
into the conscious mind when the issue of women’s ordination is raised, and
these can be traced back to a traumatic and long-repressed event in the sexual
development of the small boy. One day, the boy notices for the first time that
his sister lacks a penis. She is ‘man manque’: man who lacks, is deficient and
falls short. The effect of this discovery is shattering. In the course of the
Oedipal relationship with his mother, the boy has already discovered that he
possesses a penis and that stimulating it is pleasurable. He also discovers
that adults disapprove of his pleasurable activities and threaten him with
castration, but he pays no heed to their threats — until the day when he
discovers, through observation of his sister, that the threats are meant
seriously. In his sister he encounters one who is otherwise like him, but who
is manifestly the victim of castration. If it happened to her, might it not
also happen to him? His sexuality will need to be reorganized. He must abandon
his sexual relationship with his mother and his selfstimulation, and he must
identify himself instead with his father, to whom he has previously been
hostile and whose threat of castration he has previously ignored. Since
‘normal’ development into adult sexuality is achieved only very rarely, the
‘castration complex’ that succeeds the ‘oedipus complex’ can leave him with an
enduring although unconscious fear of the being whose lack exposed the secret
of his guilty love. He revenges himself on her by excluding her from his
sanctuaries. That is why the ‘general mind of the Church’ resists women’s
ordination.
This translation of
the general mind of the Church into Oedipal and castration complexes appears to
offer the strongest possible support for those ‘daughters of educated men’ who
wish to be admitted to the ordained ministry. Once the secret of male
resistance is out, who would any longer dare to expose his complexes to public
view? In the face of this devastating argument, the Archbishop himself will
stifle his objections. Unfortunately, there is a lifeline which must, in all
fairness, be offered to him. The Freudian tale can also be told from the
standpoint of the sister.[xiii]
One day,
while playing with her brother, the small girl notices that he has something
that she lacks. This too is a shattering discovery, and she directs her anger
against her mother. Why has her mother not equipped her with a penis? Turning
away from her mother, she now enters the Oedipal relationship with her father,
hoping to obtain from him the child which would constitute an acceptable
penis-substitute. The transfer of her affections from father to potential
husband may in due course be accomplished fairly smoothly. But, as in her
brother's case, there is considerable scope for error. The girl may refuse to
accept her lack of a penis; she may continue to behave as if she possesses one.
The tables may therefore be turned on the ‘daughters of educated men’ who wish
to enter the church or the other professions. Are they not secretly motivated
by a penis-envy that is no more creditable than their brothers’ fear of
castration? The ‘man manque’ argument can be played both ways. The result is a
stalemate in which the Archbishop and the status quo are bound to be the
winners.
Woolf is
fully aware of the ambivalence of the ‘man manque’ view. In A Room of One's
Own (1929), she gives a celebrated account of two meals, the hrst a
sumptuous lunch-party at an Oxbridge men’s college, the second a frugal dinner
at Fernham, an impoverished women’s college.18 As
she reclines in a window-seat after lunch, she notices a tailless cat padding
across the quadrangle. The Manx cat
did
look a little absurd, poor beast, without a tail, in the middle of the lawn.
Was he really born so, or had he lost his tail in an accident? The tailless
cat, though some are said to exist in the Isle of Man, is rarer than one
thinks. It is a queer animal, quaint rather than beautiful. It is strange what
a difference a tail makes — you know the sort of things one says as a lunch
party breaks up and people are hnding their coats and hats. (12)
the Sexes’ (1925), in The Penguin Freud Library
7, ed. Angela Richards, London: Penguin Books, 1991, 315—22, 331—43.
18 The lunch-party is 'distinguished not
only by its bounty and excellence but by the magical nature of its provenance,
the sense of a return to some originary plenitude now produced under the aegis
of the father. Gratification is known before desire is felt. With no command uttered,
and agency scarcely revealed, course follows course in a prelinguistic economy
of desire’ (E. Abel, Virginia Woolf, 99).
The Manx
cat from the Isle of Man is obviously an image of woman: Man/Manx = man manque.
Woman is the Man(x) who lacks a tail; the Latin penis originally meant
‘tail’. The more difficult interpretative question is who it is who resorts to
the infantile definition of woman as Manx, as man manque. The Manx cat is
noticed by the female narrator, and her amusement is without doubt a defensive
strategy intended to ward off the terrible knowledge that the Manx cat
communicates. But that knowledge is ambiguous. The narrator’s point may be:
this is how I am perceived within this all-male college — as tailless, a Manx
cat, man manque. Or her point may be: this is how I perceive myself within this
affluent, all-male college — as man manque, my physical lack corresponding to
the material and intellectual lack that I suffer through exclusion from its resources.
Is she the object of fear, or the subject of envy? Perhaps she is making both
points simultaneously, while pretending to make neither. The Manx cat is woman,
but who knows whether it represents her in terms of man’s castration complex or
her own penis-envy? The cat remains inscrutable, enjoying its power over the
Archbishop, the Professor, the general mind of the Church, and the daughters of
educated men alike. In other words, more prosaically expressed, the Manx cat
con®rms that psychology is of only limited value in discussion of women’s roles
within the church. If the Freudian tale is plausible or fantastic in one of its
versions, it is equally plausible or fantastic in the other. In practice, the
two versions of the story cancel each other out and result in stalemate and
victory for the status quo.
If anything is to be
done about the Archbishop’s eternal masculinity, we must turn to the
Commission’s theological arguments. Theology will show, perhaps, that ‘neither
is woman apart from man nor man apart from woman, in the Lord’. And, granted
the ambiguities of this statement, it will show how the phrase ‘in the Lord’
resolves them. Whatever light psychology may or may not shed upon the
relationship between man and woman, it knows nothing of how that relationship
appears ‘in the Lord’. This is a matter for theology, which is able to show
that the patriarchal church — the church as ruled by fathers and brothers, the
Archbishop’s church - has feet of clay. It does not rest on eternal
foundations. Theology does so primarily not by denouncing and negating but by
pointing to the church’s true foundation and by asking how far the Archbishop’s
church still rests on that foundation. Theology does all this even in the hands
of a Commission which, although it will not venture a dogmatic denial of woman’s
capacity for ordained ministry, is convinced that any change to the status quo
would be quite inappropriate now or in the foreseeable future.
‘In the Lord’ refers
us not to a patriarchal ruler but to Jesus.[xiv] Compelled to turn to the New
Testament in order to address the question put to them, the Commission found
that ‘the Gospels show us that our Lord regarded men and women alike as members
of the same spiritual kingdom, as children of God’s family, and as possessors
of the same spiritual capacities . . . ’ (quoted in Three Guineas,
249-50). ‘It would seem then that the founder of Christianity believed that
neither training nor sex was needed for this profession’, and that his belief
was rightly interpreted and summarized in the affirmation that ‘there is neither
male nor female: for ye are all one in Christ Jesus’ (250). The divine gift was
bestowed upon carpenters, fishermen, but also on women:
As
the Commission points out there can be no doubt that in those early days there
were prophetesses - women upon whom the divine gift had descended. Also they
were allowed to preach. St Paul, for example, lays it down that women, when
praying in public, should be veiled. ‘The implication is that if veiled a woman
might prophesy [i.e. preach] and lead in prayer.’ How then can they be excluded
from the priesthood since they were once thought fit by the founder of the
religion and by one of his apostles to preach? That was the question, and the
Commission solved it by appealing not to the mind of the founder, but to the
mind of the Church. That, of course, involved a distinction. For the mind of
the Church had to be interpreted by another mind, and that mind was St Paul’s
mind; and St Paul, in interpreting that mind, changed his mind. (250)
The
Pauline veil is no longer an ambivalent symbol of division, as it is elsewhere
in Woolf's text; it represents woman's authority to proclaim, in accordance
with the mind of Christ. However, the authorization was quickly revoked. The
Commission appealed to the prohibition of 1 Timothy 2.12 — whether the author
be ‘St Paul or another' ± to justify their claim that the church has changed
its mind. (They might also have appealed to 1 Cor. 14.34±35, with the same
qualification.) Woolf comments:
That,
it may frankly be said, is not so satisfactory as it might be; for we cannot
altogether reconcile the ruling of St Paul, or another, with the ruling of
Christ himself who ‘regarded men and women alike as members of the same
spiritual kingdom . . . and as possessors of the same spiritual capacities’.
But it is futile to quibble over the meaning of words, when we are so soon in
the presence of facts. Whatever Christ meant, or St Paul meant, the fact was
that in the fourth or ®fth century the profession of religion had become so
highly organized that . . . the prophet or prophetess whose message was
voluntary and untaught became extinct; and their places were taken by the three
orders of bishops, priests and deacons, who are invariably men . . . (25O-I)
If we
turn from exegetical debates to facts, we find (for example) that whereas an
archbishop currently receives a salary of £15,000 and a bishop £10,000, a
deaconess or a parish worker receives no more than £150 a year in recognition
of her labours (252). In the church as elsewhere, salary differentials must be
taken as a measure of the value ascribed to different types of paid work, and
it is therefore hard to avoid the conclusion that the church values the work of
men much more highly than the work of women. That is the material fact, and the
Commission had no intention of allowing theology or the founder of Christianity
to interfere with it.[xv]
Because the church
must serve as a symbol of patriarchy in transcendental clothing, Woolf is
content to allow the Commission to acquiesce in the status quo. The Church of
England has refused to admit women to the ordained ministry ± and 'long may she
exclude us!' (207). The Outsider is the mirror-image of the Archbishop. They
complement one another and are necessary to one another, so that even here
woman is not apart from man nor man from woman ± precisely at the point where
man's self-de®nition excludes woman and woman's retaliatory and defensive
self-de®nition excludes men. But instead of de®ning herself over against the
patriarchal monolith, the Outsider might have chosen to exploit the admission
that ± however impressive it may appear ± the monolith is in fact a mere facade
that knowingly conceals the reality it is supposed to represent. The mind of
the church must conform to the mind of Christ. The admission that the church
has changed its mind, and that the mind that it has changed is the mind of
Christ, is an admission of error far more damning than the 'infantile fixation'
theory.
It is the mind of
Christ that exposes the perversity of the mind of the church, and not the
Freudian aetiology. The strong and hostile feelings that the issue of women's
ministry arouses are indeed symptomatic of a repressed originary experience.
But this experience is not an infantile theory about bodily differentiation but
the original encounter with Christ, in whom there is neither male nor female,
and in whom ± in the absence of hierarchical and essentialist dehnitions of
maleness and femaleness ± man and woman are dehned not as apart from one
another but in relation to one another. The fact of repression indicates that
this encounter too could be experienced as a traumatic threat of castration:
and this repression is the origin of the Archbishop's eternal masculinity. Yet
if there is ± to return to the testimony of the Bishop of Birmingham ± a
'spirit of Christ' that even now shapes a mode of being in the world that
conforms to the mind of Christ, there is no reason to think that the
Archbishop's position is secure. On the contrary, his masculinity is in
jeopardy.
According to the
Commission, 'the Gospels show us that our Lord regarded men and women alike as
members of the same spiritual kingdom, as children of God's family, and as
possessors of the same spiritual capacities . . . ’ In this deceptively bland
statement, we may ®nd the repressed moment of trauma that the spirit of Christ
seeks to expose and heal. The phrase ‘children of God’s family’ is not simply
pious rhetoric. It alludes to the words of Jesus: ‘Truly I say to you, unless
you turn and become like children, you will never enter the kingdom of heaven’
(Matt. 18.3). It is here that the original, repressed threat is to be found.
The point of the saying is not to idealize childhood or to offer a refuge from
adult reality in infantile fantasy. Instead, Jesus articulates the possibility
and the promise that the long historical process in which adult gendered
identity is constructed and ®xed may be unravelled and undone, so that identity
may be recreated. The parabolic ®gure of the child represents here the human whose
identity is fluid and malleable, potential rather than actual, not yet
solidi®ed and ®xed. According to the parable, an old history of
identity-formation is to be undone and superseded by a new history in which the
product of the old history is radically reshaped. To submit oneself to that new
history is to enter the kingdom of heaven. The ®xed identity that emerges from
the primary history is, of course, a gendered identity, and it now becomes
clear how it is that Jesus’ utterance may be heard as a threat of castration.
Indeed, the old identity is bound to perceive it as such, and from its own
standpoint it is not wrong to do so. Jesus commands that the bodily member that
leads one into sin be cut off (5.29-30). He commends those who have made themselves
eunuchs for the sake of the kingdom of heaven (19.12). Indeed, he himself
wields the knife: he has come not to bring peace but a sword (10.34).[xvi]
Jesus poses a threat
to the gendered identities that history has laboriously constructed and passed
off as nature. He calls for men and women to turn from them and to become again
like children so that their identities may be recreated. In particular, Jesus
is a threat to masculine gendered identity, the social construct
arbitrarily erected on the basis of the inalienable maleness and femaleness
given in creation. He challenges the belief that masculine identity entails the
exclusion of women from the public sphere, just as he challenges the related
belief that masculine identity (‘manliness’, ‘virility’) is constituted by the
violence of war and its surrogates. He comes to disturb the peace of masculine
complacency and feminine acquiescence, not because his goal is destruction for
his own sake but in order to clear the ground for new, more flexible constructs
in which men and women learn to relate to one another ‘in the Lord’ and in the
light of the kingdom of heaven that is creation’s goal.
saying (in its Marcan form, Mk.
10.15) is that 'the child/slave who occupies the lowest place within
patriarchal structures becomes the primary paradigm for true discipleship . . .
This saying is not an invitation to childlike innocence and naivete but a
challenge to relinquish all claims of power and domination over others’ (In
Memory of Her: A Feminist Theological Reconstruction of Christian Origins,
London: SCM Press, 1983, 148).
CHAPTER
TWO
The veil
may be a symbol of division. It can represent a gendered distribution of space,
demarcating the public and the private realms in which man and woman
respectively have their being. It can be resented because of the restrictions
it enforces, and cherished as the source of wisdom and insight. Certain Pauline
or deutero-Pauline texts, enjoining silence and docility as the conditions of
woman's marginal participation in the public sphere, make this a plausible
interpretation of the Pauline image. On closer reading of the Pauline text,
however, it appears that the veil is the symbol not of woman's enforced silence
but of her authority to speak ± to speak, indeed, to and from God on behalf of
the congregation, to declare in her own voice the word of the Lord and the
answering human word. ‘Every woman praying or prophesying with uncovered head
dishonours her head’ (i Cor. 11.5). Granted that woman speaks and must speak to
and from God, the veil is the mark of her right to do so. Woman ‘must have
authority on the head . . . ’ (v. 10), and the veil is that authority —
assuming what must later be demonstrated, that the veil is indeed the issue
here. The speech that the veil authorizes is not a marginal speech that occurs
behind closed doors but a speech that belongs at the heart of the public life
of the worshipping congregation. But why is this speech subjected to the
condition of the veil? And how is it that the veil that authorizes speech can
also be seen — with some plausibility — to deny speech and to enjoin silence?
In the face of this
paradox, it is inappropriate to protest the text’s innocence and to lay the
blame on its ‘male interpreters’ and on the deutero-Pauline gloss in 1
Corinthians 14.34—5 that has led them astray. It is equally inappropriate to
welcome the veil and the exclusion as negative conditions for a space 'apart
from man' in which woman subjects man's works to silent yet critical scrutiny.
In the Lord, woman is not apart from man nor man from woman, and that
togetherness is distorted and undermined if her voice is not heard at the
heart of the public space of worship. To anticipate: the veil is the condition
of woman's speech in that it intercepts and prohibits the male gaze that would
convert her into an object and prevent her recognition as a speaking subject.
It is agape and not eros that must rule in the public sphere of the
congregation, and for that reason the veil is interposed as the condition of
woman's speech and of man's listening to woman's speech ± the speech not of an
abstract 'autonomous subject' but of one who has been freed by the gospel to
declare in her own language the mighty works of God. The veil is a symbol
directed at man. In its blankness it admonishes him to hear the word of the
Lord in the medium of a woman's voice and to make her response to this word his
own. In order that he may listen and not look, it imposes on him the
humiliation of a blindfold. For the sake of the agape that is the condition of
true speaking and hearing within the body of Christ, eros ± or woman as
construed by the erotic male gaze ± must be veiled.
Paul's attempt to
interpose the veil was questionable not only culturally and politically but
also theologically ± as he himself later tacitly acknowledges. In the new
covenant, he will argue, it is proper that women and men should behold the
glory of the Lord with unveiled face; it is only the Law that speaks from
behind a veil, and the Law has now reached its limit (2 Cor. 3.12—18). Yet,
beneath the surface of the awkward, assertive and embarrassed Pauline
discourse, genuine theological concerns are still recognizable.[xvii]
SHAMING THE HEAD [VERSES 2 ± 6)
1
praise you because you remember
all that I taught and, just as I delivered them to you, you observe the
traditions
(1 Cor. 11.2). Where, in spite of this, traditions have not been faithfully
observed, Paul does not praise. He is sharply critical, as in the case of the
Corinthian practice of the Lord’s Supper (11.17-34): ‘As for the following
instructions, I do not praise you, because your assembling together is
not for the better but for the worse’ (v. 17). It seems likely that the
uncovered heads of the Corinthian women represent not an aberration but the
established tradition at Corinth, which Paul now seeks to change — in the
light, perhaps, of the universal practice of ‘the churches of God’ elsewhere
(v. 16). ‘But I want you to know. . . ’ (v. 3) signals the intention not of
correcting an abuse but of announcing a supplement to the traditions that will
interrupt and modify existing practice. To continue to observe the traditions
‘just as I delivered them to you’ would now be to disobey the living voice of
the apostle.2
Paul's Rhetoric,
Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1990). Fiorenza is rightly critical of
interpreters who 'characterize the Corinthians as foolish, immature, arrogant,
divisive, individualistic, unrealistic illusionists, libertine enthusiasts, or
boasting spiritualists who misunderstand the preaching of Paul in terms of
''realized eschatology’’’ (389). A cursory look at scholarship on 1 Corinthians
indicates that Paul is a skilled rhetorician, who, throughout the centuries,
has reached his goal of persuading his audience that he is right and that the
''others’’ are wrong’ (390). Fiorenza wishes to distinguish between 'the
historical argumentative situation, the implied or inscribed rhetorical
situation as well as the rhetorical situation of contemporary interpretations’
(388): a 'historical argumentative situation’ marked by the genesis of an
incipient feminist theology at Corinth can both be reconstructed from the
Pauline text and used to counter the 'implied or inscribed rhetorical
situation’ as rendered in that text. Two main problems arise at this point. First,
the project of recovering the suppressed voices of early Christian women
reflects historical-critical scholarship’s over-optimistic assessment of its
own ability to reconstruct entire historical complexes from the few ambiguous
fragments that survive. Second, the polarity of androcentric text and
suppressed voices simply reverses the privileging of the Pauline perspective
over that of his addressees, and assigns to the interpreter the privileged role
of opponent of the text. But a generalized 'hermeneutic of suspicion’ along
these lines may not be the most appropriate or effective strategy for
theological reflection on issues of gender.
2 The text does not support the view
that an 'overrealized eschatology’ has 'involved some kind of breakdown in the
distinction between the sexes’, as women at Corinth argued for the right to
pray and prophesy 'without the customary ''head covering’’ or ''hairstyle’’’
(G. Fee, The First Epistle to the Corinthians, NICNT, Grand Rapids: Eerdmans,
1987, 498). This view derives from the assumption that a coherent, distinctive But I
want you to know that the head of every man is Christ, the head of woman is
man, and the head of Christ is God (v. 3). The traditions as
originally delivered and faithfully maintained are interrupted by a threefold
dogmatic statement that lends itself to rearrangement in the form of a
hierarchy. If the third statement is placed at the beginning, the result is a descending
hierarchy that runs from God to Christ to man to woman. If the ®rst statement
is placed second, the result is an ascending hierarchy, from woman to
man to Christ to God. Rearranged like this, the threefold statement serves as a
pattern for later Christian or pseudoChristian accounts of being as hierarchy
and discloses the simple assumptions about gender that will so often underlie
their apparent complexities. It also indicates that a hierarchical account of
gender, in which male and female are related to one another as higher to lower,
may be sustained by what will later be identified as an ‘Arian’ christology in
which human preeminence and subordination ®nd their ontological grounding in
the relation of God to Christ. Hierarchical accounts of being require not only
relationships of pre-eminence and subordination but also a chain of connections
that links the highest member in the series with the lowest and blurs the
absolute distinction between creator and creature. Yet these world-views will
often be unconscious of their Arian or neo-Platonic affinities. They will feel
no need to defend themselves against the charge of heterodoxy, and will for
centuries be accepted as authentically Christian. Although the Pauline
statement lends itself to hierarchical rearrangement along these lines,
it is not its intention to assert any such account of being as
hierarchy. As the threefold statement stands, there is no descending or
ascending hierarchy: only a series of assertions in which a ‘head’ is assigned
to man, to woman and to Christ. The reference is probably to pre-eminence and
authority rather than to relations of origin.3 The sequel will show that it is only
the ®rst two
Corinthian theology can be
deduced from i Corinthians and used as the primary background for the
interpretation of the letter.
3 The claim that kephale in v. 3
means 'source’ is rejected by David Horrell, The Social Ethos of the
Corinthian Correspondence: Interest and Ideology from 1 Corinthians to 1
Clement, assertions
that play any role in the argument, that they are applied to the single issue
of the covering or uncovering of the head, and that the covering of the head
gives woman the ‘authority’ to proclaim the word of God to the congregation
irrespective of her relation to any other ‘head’. The fact that ‘the head of
woman is man’ is a potential deterrent to woman’s proclamation which the
covering of her head will effectively nullify. As a theological basis for the
proposed new custom, the threefold statement of verse 3 is entirely
unconvincing in the light of the radical divine deconstruction of worldly
dualities of wisdom and folly, power and weakness, that has earlier been
announced (1 Cor. 1.18—31). Yet the grounding of the new custom in woman’s
relationship to man remains signihcant, however poorly this relationship is
here articulated.
Every
man praying or prophesying with his head covered shames his head (v. 4). ‘With his
head covered’ translates kata kephales echon (‘having down the head’).
The meaning of this phrase is established by Esther 6.12, where, after his
defeat by Mordecai the Jew, Haman returns to his home grieving kata
kephales: the underlying Hebrew can only refer to the covering of the head
as a sign of mourning, and a later Septuagintal editor rightly paraphrases the
cryptic Greek phrase as katakekalummenos ke- phalen, ‘[his] head
covered’. That men cover their heads in situations of distress is conhrmed by
the example of David who, according to Josephus, covered himself (katakalupsamenou)
as he mourned the death of Absalom (Antiquities, vii.254). Paul,
however, is uninterested in the mourning custom: his concern is with the
covering of the head while speaking to or from God in the midst of the
assembly.
It now
becomes clear that the ‘head’ metaphors of the previous verse arise out of this
concern with the literal, physical head. The metaphors (Christ as head, man as
head) provide the
Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1996,
170 — 1. Horrell notes that Paul uses this word 'not to talk about authority
and subordination but precisely because he wants to talk about the way
in which men and women must attire their kephale in worship.
Nevertheless, the theological legitimation which the kephaloe analogy
provides clearly gives man priority over woman’ (171).
key to
the word-play of the following verses, in which literal and metaphorical
referents are juxtaposed. In the light of this key, it is clear that the head
that is shamed is not the head that is covered. The covered male head shames
Christ, who is the head of every man. Paul wishes to impose the covering of the
head on women but not on men, and the hypothetical notion of the covered male
head serves to justify the distinction the new custom draws between men and
women.[xviii] The objection is anticipated that, if women are to
cover their heads, then men should do likewise; and this objection is ruled out
on the grounds that the physical heads of men and women represent different
metaphorical realities that require the uncovering of the one and the covering
of the other. But if man (the head of woman) is shamed by her uncovered head,
why is Christ (the head of man) shamed when his head is covered? What is it
about the relation of woman to her ‘head’ that requires the covering of her
physical head, when the relation of man to his ‘head’ prohibits any such
covering? To be subject to a ‘head’ does not in itself entail the covering of
the physical head. At this point, pure arbitrariness appears to reign; in other
words, the underlying issue is still completely unclear.
But
every woman praying or prophesying with head uncovered shames her head. . . (v. 5a). In recent
scholarship, ‘uncovered’ is often taken to mean ‘with unbound hair’ rather than
‘unveiled’, on the basis of Septuagintal usage. The term akatakaluptos
(‘uncovered’) occurs only in Leviticus 13.45, where the leper is instructed to
wear torn clothes and to leave his head uncovered (he kephale autou
akatakaluptos, an accurate rendering of the Hebrew); that is, he is to let
his hair hang loose. But the term does not refer to loose hair as such, but to
loose hair as the uncovering of a head that has previously been covered ± perhaps
by an arrangement of the hair, but equally possibly by an article of clothing
such as a turban. This Septuagintal usage is quite compatible with the
traditional view that the woman who prays or prophesies with uncovered head is
‘uncovered’ in the sense that she does not wear a veil. This view is conhrmed
by the Septuagintal use of the verb katakaluptein, which occurs three
times in 1 Corinthians 11.6—7, and the cognate noun katakalumma. In
Genesis 38.15, the patriarch Judah mistakes his daughter-in-law Tamar for a
prostitute because her face was covered (katekalupsato gar to prosopon
autes): here the reference can only be to a veil. At the trial of Susanna,
the elders who falsely accuse her of adultery demand that her face be unveiled
(Sus. 32: hoi de paranomoi ekeleusan apokaluphthenai auten, en gar
katakekalummene). As for the noun, the ‘virgin daughter of Babylon’ is
commanded in Isaiah 47.2 to put off her veil (apokalupsai to katakalumma
sou). Septuagintal usage seems conclusively in favour of the traditional
interpretation of this passage: the Corinthian women’s headcovering is
specihcally a covering for the face. Like Moses but unlike other men,
they are to conceal their face behind a veil (kalumma, 2 Cor. 3.13).5
5 W. Schrage’s arguments in favour of
the 'unbound hair’ view represent a broad consensus in recent scholarship (Der
Erste Brief an die Kormther (1 Kor. 6,12—11,16), EKK vii/2, Solothurn and
Dusseldorf: Benziger Verlag AG; Neukirchen-Vluyn: Neukirch- ener Verlag des
Erziehungsvereins GmbH, 1995, 491—4). (1) Paul does not mention the veil in
this passage, but he does mention the topic of hair-length (vv. 4, 6, 14 ± 15).
(2) There is extensive evidence that women took part in Graeco-Roman religious
rites with unbound hair. (3) The term akatakaluptos is found in the LXX
only in Lev. 13.45, where it refers to unbound hair. It is remarkable how Lev.
13.45 is so often cited without any reference to Septuagintal usage of katakaluptein,
which Paul uses three times in 1 Cor. 11.6 — 7. As for the ®rst point, the
celebration of woman’s long hair as her 'glory’ (v. 15) is hardly an effective
argument against unbound hair. The references to hair-length must be
understood as supporting arguments for the imposition of the veil. If the
'unbound hair’ interpretation is preferred, however, the interpretation of the
passage in terms of the erotic attraction of man to woman is still viable. In
one of the parabolic visions of the Shepherd of Hermas, there appear
'twelve women, very beautiful to look at, clothed in black, girded, and their
shoulders bare and their hair
It is
true that Moses’ veil is said to cover his ‘face’ (prosopon), whereas
the Corinthian women are to cover their ‘head’ (kephale). This might
suggest a form of head-covering that leaves the face free. The new custom is
explicitly associated with the ‘head’ in verses 5, 7, 10; the influence of the
head imagery of verse 3 is apparent in the wordplay of verse 5, and perhaps
still in verse 7. But Paul can also speak of woman’s being ‘covered’ in absolute
terms and without specific reference to the head (ei gar ou katakaluptetai
gune, v. 6; katakaluptestho, v. 6; gunaika akataka- lupton,
v. 13); this absolute usage is exactly parallel to Susanna 32, which can only
refer to the face. Cognate terminology in 2 Corinthians 3.12-18 explicitly
refers to the face (me anakalupto- menon, v. 14; anakekalummeno
prosopo, v. 18; kalumma, vv. 13, 14, 15, 16; cf. kekalummenon,
4.3).6
The
passage from 1 Corinthians was associated with the veiling of women at least as
early as the latter part of the second century (well before Tertullian’s
extensive treatment of it, which will be discussed later). In 1 Corinthians
11.10, Irenaeus attests a reading that substitutes kalumma for exousia:
‘For this reason a woman should have a veil upon her head . . . ’ (Adversus
haereses, i.8.2). Irenaeus cites a gnostic exegesis of the text in which it
is linked with Moses’ veil as an indication that Achamoth (the misshapen
feminine being that resulted from the passion of Sophia (i.4)) ‘drew a veil
over herself through modesty’ at the
loose [tas trichas lelumenai].
And these women looked to me to be cruel’ (sim. ix.9.5). Later, certain
of the 'servants of God’ are 'deceived by the beauty of these women’ with their
'loose hair’ (ix.13.7—9). Hermas and his readers obviously recognize unbound
hair as a symbol of illicit sexual attraction.
6 The view that the head-covering does
not include the face is represented by C. Wolff: 'Bei der Kopfdeckung, auf die
korinthische Frauen verzichteten, handelt es sich nicht um einen das Antlitz
verhullenden Schleier; denn Paulus spricht nicht von einer Verhullung des
Gesichtes, sondern vom Bedecken des Kopfes’ (Der erste Brief des Paulus an
die Korinther, ThHKNT 7/11, Berlin: Evangelische Verlagsanstalt, 1982, 67).
Wolff appeals to evidence from the synagogue at Dura Europos for a form of
head-covering that leaves the face free. A. Jaubert shows that later Jewish
texts require the covering of the hair on the grounds that 'les cheveux sont un
ornement pour la femme mais un danger pour l’homme, parce qu’ils sont pour lui
un attrait’ ('Le Voile des Femmes [I Cor. XI.2—16]’, NTS 18 (1971 — 2),
419—30; 425 — 6). Although my own interpretation of the passage assumes that
the head-covering includes a covering of the face, the crucial point is
the basis of the head-covering in the erotic attraction of the male for the
female.
approach
of the masculine Saviour from above (i.8.2). This reading of 1 Corinthians
11.10 therefore predates Irenaeus and may be traced back to Valentinus or his
disciple Ptolemaeus (Adv. haer., i.1.2). Irenaeus does not dissent from
the association of the Pauline passage with the veil, and later indicates that
he has his own reasons for interest in the passage. In opposition to
‘Montanist’ appeal to the Johannine theme of the coming of the Paraclete, some
have argued that the Gospel of John itself should be rejected. Irenaeus is
scathing: ‘Wretched men indeed! who wish to be pseudo-prophets, indeed, but who
set aside the gift of prophecy from the church . . . We must conclude that
these men cannot admit the Apostle Paul either: for in his Epistle to the
Corinthians he speaks expressly of prophetical gifts and recognizes men and
women prophesying in the church’ (iii.11.9). This defence of women prophets
demonstrates Irenaeus’ own Montanist sympathies; and in the light of his
reading of 1 Corinthians 11.10, it is likely that he associates the women
prophets of the Pauline text with the veil.[xix]
Paul links the
absence of this head-covering with ‘shame’. The unveiled woman ‘shames her
head’ (kataischunei ten kephalen antes, 1 Cor. 11.5, a reference to her
husband or perhaps to ‘man’ in general). This ‘shame’ appears to be the shame
of physical nakedness. (If so, this is a further indication that the
head-covering conceals the face, and not just the hair. For Paul, woman’s hair
is already equivalent to a ‘garment’ (peribolaion, v. 15), and the
absence of a hair-covering cannot be associated with nakedness and shame.)
Shame and nakedness can be virtual synonyms. The daughter of Babylon is to put
off her veil, strip off her robe and uncover her legs, so that ‘your shame
shall be seen [anakaluphthesetai he aischune sou]’ (Is. 47.2-3). The
shame of nakedness arises from the uncovering of the face no less than the
legs, and - although the passive verb conceals this - it also presupposes the
presence of a male onlooker who makes the virgin daughter of Babylon the object
of his contemptuous and lustful gaze. The correlation of the naked female face
with the desiring male onlooker is, however, more explicit in the story of
Susanna, which at several points offers crucial insights into the meaning of
the Pauline text.
Susanna
is a devout woman of great beauty (kale sphodra kai phoboumene ton kurion,
Sus. 2) who becomes the object of lustful infatuation. Seeing her walking each
day in her husband's garden, two elders ± appointed that year as judges of the
people ± are overcome with desire for her. One hot day she sends her maids to
fetch oil and ointments so that she may bathe, and ®nds herself trapped by the
elders who have secretly been watching her: if she will not lie with them, they
will testify that they caught her in the act of adultery with a young man. She
chooses ‘not to sin in the sight of the Lord', and is duly accused. The trial
is held the next day at her husband's house, and Susanna is called in — a
woman, we are reminded, ‘of great delicacy and beautiful in appearance [truphera
sphodra kai kale te eidei] (v. 31). ‘And the wicked men commanded her to be
unveiled [apokaluphthenai] — for she was veiled [en gar katakekalum-
mene] — so that they might be satished with her beauty [hopes
emplesthosin tou kallous autes]. But her family [hoi par' autes] and
all who saw her wept' (vv. 32-3). Susanna is convicted, but is saved as she is
led out to die by the intervention of Daniel, who demonstrates that the elders'
testimony is false.[xx]
The
moment of unveiling is the satisfaction of the elders' desire for Susanna.
Having failed to persuade her to lie with them, the ‘desire' they announce to
her (en epithumia sou esmen, v. 21) remains unfulhlled. But the sight of
her naked, unveiled face at her trial provides a substitute for what Susanna
refused them: in a climactic moment, they look and are satished. At this point,
however, a persistent misreading of the text comes to light. The text does not
say that Susanna was naked when the elders accosted her in the garden. She had
announced her intention to bathe, she had sent her servants out to fetch oil
and ointments, and, ‘when the maids had gone out, the two elders rose and ran
to her . . . ’ (v. 19). The elders must act during the brief interval when the
maids are absent; they have no time to watch Susanna undress and enter the
water, and the text says nothing of this. In any case, it is perhaps the maids
who will undress her. Yet it is generally assumed that Susanna, like Eve, was
naked in the garden (described here as a paradeisos); and the real
moment of nakedness — the unveiling of the face at the trial - is downplayed.[xxi]
The non-existent
moment is captured by Rembrandt, who painted it twice. In the earlier version
(c. 1637), the naked Susanna rises from a seated position in order to enter her
bath, slipping her shoes off her feet as she does so. Behind her lie her
clothes, although with her right hand she continues to clutch the lower part of
a garment across her thigh. Her left hand (nearest the viewer) crosses her
breast in order to disentangle her long hair. Bracelets, necklace and head-band
signify her wealth. Her face is turned towards the viewer, and she shows no
apprehension. But in the dense foliage behind her there is concealed a single
male face that watches her — the dark alter ego, perhaps, of the male
viewer, who also looks at her in her nakedness. In the later painting (1647),
Susanna is stepping into the water and the elders have now emerged from their
concealment. Immediately behind her, the first of them grasps with his left
hand the robe with which she conceals her modesty, as if to pull it away from
her. His clenched right hand expresses his tense excitement, while, behind him,
the face of the second elder betrays his pleasure at the spectacle — forgetful
now of the physical weakness of age which compels him to walk with the aid of a
stick. Susanna’s anxious face is turned towards the viewer, as if appealing for
help.
Why has the artist
insinuated this moment of nakedness into the text, so plausibly that its later
readers continue to believe that they have found it there?
In the background of
both paintings there stands a large building with a tower. If the tower can be
seen from Susanna's garden, then Susanna can be seen from the tower. In these
paintings, however, the tower remains unoccupied ± although a sketch for the
later one replaces it with a distant stone column upon which a statue of a male
®gure surveys the scene. This ®gure has, as it were, crossed over from another
painting (1643), in which King David watches from a tower in his palace as the
naked Bathsheba prepares for her bath. It is the biblical narrative of David
and Bathsheba that underlies the conversion of Susanna's intention to take a
bath into these visions of her naked form exposed to male onlookers. But the
result of this insertion from another narrative is that the lifting of
Susanna's veil at her trial has hardly been noticed. The artist knows of it,
but he has allowed this motif too to wander into another painting: for in his
rendering of the encounter between Christ and the woman taken in adultery
(1644), the elder who tells of the kneeling woman's sin raises the veil from
her face as he does so ± enabling onlookers and viewers to ®nd their satisfaction
in her humiliated and threatened beauty. The artist has rightly sensed actual
af®nities between the story of Susanna and the earlier and later narratives,
but he has chosen to develop them in such a way that the projection of
Bathsheba's naked form into Susanna's garden displaces the unveiling-motif into
the Johannine narrative. There are profound reasons for his choice. For the
artistic tradition in which he stands, the primary erotic object is not the
unveiled female face but the unveiled female body. Susanna's unveiled face is
not without erotic interest, as her surrogate in the rendering of the Johan-
nine story indicates. But in the presence of Christ, eros must take subdued
forms. In the case of Susanna, whose physical beauty the narrative itself twice
emphasizes, the expressed intention to take a bath is suf®cient textual basis
for the insertion of the Bathsheba motif of full bodily unveiling. So Susanna
comes to share Bathsheba's nakedness, just as she shares her exposure to a male
gaze that is represented within the painting itself.10
In the
biblical Susanna narrative the links with Bathsheba are real but marginal, and
the erotic climax occurs not in the garden but in the unveiling of the face.
The narrator distances himself and his readers from the elders' erotic
satisfaction by emphasizing their depravity, and by presenting a more appropriate
response to Susanna's humiliation in the form of her weeping family (v. 33).
Yet the story does presuppose a tradition in which the female face is an object
of such intense erotic concern that, in the public realm outside the immediate
sphere of the family, it must be concealed behind a veil. Susanna's entire
bodily beauty is concentrated in her face, and the narrative assumes that the
uncovering of the face is itself suf®cient to satisfy male desire. That is why
her family weeps. And that is also why ‘every woman who prays or prophesies
with uncovered head shames her head'. Susanna is shamed by her own public
unveiling, and her parents, husband, children and relatives share in her
shaming. Susanna was unveiled under duress, but the woman who deliberately
appears in public with unveiled face, displaying herself as the object of the
erotic male gaze, must be held responsible for the shame that falls especially
upon her husband. Or so one might conclude if, like Paul, one shared the
cultural assumptions implied in the Susanna narrative.
It is
now clear why men who pray and prophesy must do so with uncovered head whereas
women must conceal their face behind a veil. Eros is construed asymmetrically
as the desire of the male subject for the female object, aroused and perhaps
even satished by an act of looking that transhxes its object, depriving it of
subjectivity and movement and subjecting it to its own power. Such a construal
is admittedly an abstraction, indeed a fantasy; for the male gaze is always
embedded in
10 According to M. Miles, depictions of
Susanna in western art 'attempt to reproduce, in the eyes of an assumed male
viewer, the Elders' intense erotic attraction, projected and displayed on
Susanna's flesh . . . Viewers are directed — trained — by the management of
lights and shadows to see Susanna as object, even as cause, of male desire' (Carnal
Knowing: Female Nakedness and Religious Meaning in the Christian West, Boston:
Beacon Press, 1989, 123). networks
of relationships in which its potential and actual objects continue to exercise
their subjectivity and their relative freedom of movement. The art-work that
holds the naked female form steady and immobilized before the eyes of the male
viewer corresponds to a fantasy that is only imperfectly realized within actual
erotic relationships. In claiming that the woman who prays or prophesies with
unveiled face makes herself the object of the male gaze, Paul need not assume
that eros will simply overwhelm and erase her speech, making it inaudible as
the eye supplants the ear; but he must assume that the availability of the
look may distort and impair the reception of her speech. She speaks the word of
the Lord or the human response to that word, but her face as it appears to the
gaze of eros is incommensurate with that speech. It is a barrier to hearing ±
not because of what it is in itself but because of the mode of its appearance
as the passive object of erotic fantasy. The purpose of the veil is to remove
the hindrance to reception by depriving the fantasy of its object ± not as a
®rst step towards refusing woman the right to speak at all, as the unfortunate
later gloss would have us believe (1 Cor. 14.34-5), but precisely in order to
secure that right to speak and to ensure that what is spoken is duly heard.
Paul knows that the
new custom he proposes will be contentious (11.16). It will perhaps be seen as
representing ‘eastern’ and ‘Asian’ cultural assumptions that are alien to the
Greeks and the west.[xxii] But objections to it are not simply an expression
of cultural differences; there are also good theological reasons why the
proposed new custom should be rejected. Is it really the case that in eros the
male is the active subject and the female the passive object? May a woman not
look at a man and desire him, and, if so, ought not men to conceal their
faces behind a veil when they pray or prophesy? In fact, the new custom grossly
exaggerates the potential of the look to hinder the reception of the word. It
insults women by compelling them to reckon with the male look as a fundamental
problem of their
existence,
even within the sphere of the Christian congregation. It insults men by
stereotyping them as the helpless victims of eros, depriving them of true
subjectivity by offering them protection from a false subjectivity that they
may well disown. It undermines the familial dimension of the Christian
community, within which the fellow-Christian is addressed as ‘brother’ or
‘sister’. It is a barrier not so much to eros as to agape. Within the Christian
congregation, it must surely be possible for men and women to behold the glory
of the Lord together, with unveiled faces.
For
these or other reasons, most subsequent Christian communities have not been
persuaded by Paul’s argument here.12 Yet, clumsy and ill-conceived though it surely is,
this passage is not simply to be rejected as the later passages that silence
women altogether are to be rejected. The Pauline veil may be taken to represent
not a viable practical proposal but an invitation to think through the
difference between eros and agape, on the assumption that genuine concerns of
individual and corporate Christian existence may indeed be bound up with this
distinction. We may therefore persist in the attempt to hear what Paul is
saying, from behind the veil of his questionable theological arguments.
Every
woman praying or prophesying with uncovered head shames her head; it is one and
the same thing as having herself shaved. If a woman refuses to veil herself,
let her have her hair cut short. But if short hair or shaven head is
shamefulfor a woman, let her veil herself (vv. 5-6). Paul cannot rely on
his readers to agree that woman’s unveiled face is an occasion for shame, and
he therefore attempts an argument by analogy. They will not deny that it is
shameful for a woman to have her hair cut short or her head shaved altogether,
even though that is not the case with a man (v. 14). But what is the precise
mechanism of shame here? The shame is the shame of nakedness. Hair is given to
a woman ‘for a covering’ (v. 15), as a garment provided by nature itself so
that the shame of her nakedness may not be seen. It is just a small step,
although a
12 The history of the interpretation of
this passage is summarized in W. Schrage, I Korinther, 2.525—41. necessary
one, from the covering of woman’s head by her hair to the covering of her face
with a veil.
Shame-language
proves a more useful support for the new custom than the christologically
oriented ‘head’ metaphors of verse 3, which have now dropped out of sight. But
an attempt is now made to find an alternative theological basis for the new
custom in the created order as described in Genesis 1-2 (vv. 7—12). Despite the
appearance of seemingly arbitrary and inconsistent statements here, the
theological substance of this attempt to delimit eros from agape as the basis
for the relation of man and woman ‘in the Lord’ deserves close attention.
THE GLORY OF MAN [VERSES 7-9)
For
man ought not to cover his head, since he is the image and glory of God; but
woman is the glory of man
(v. 7). Is this a second hierarchy in the making (God—man—woman), similar to
the first although grounded not in christology but in the created order? Is
woman now deprived of her participation in the image of God, which in Genesis
de®nes her humanity as a co-humanity shared with man? The passage lends itself
to such a reading, it drifts towards it without suf®cient forethought, but it
is not this that it intends to say. It intends to support the claim of the
preceding verses that the veil is proper to woman but improper to man, and we
may expect to find here not so much a ‘hierarchy’ as a further development of
the theme we have already identified: the asymmetrical account of eros in which
the male subject hxes his gaze on a female object. This account may be
one-sided and flawed, but it is not unrelated to the problematic realities of
eros — whether these stem from nature, from culture or from both.
Man and woman were
previously distinguished by their relation to different ‘heads’; now they are
distinguished as the ‘glory’ of their respective ‘heads’. The head of man is
Christ and the head of Christ is God; the head of woman is man. If, in the
context of creation, we omit ‘Christ’ as the connecting link between man and
God, a symmetrical pattern emerges. Man’s head is (indirectly) God, woman’s
head is man; man is God’s glory and woman is man’s glory. Man would dishonour
his head by covering his head, woman would dishonour her head by leaving her
head uncovered; man's status as the glory of God forbids his covering his head,
woman's status as the glory of man forbids her to appear with uncovered head.
The crucial term in this elegant but obscure patterning is perhaps ‘glory' (doxa).
Man is ‘image and glory of God': ‘glory' is intended to gloss the scriptural
term, ‘image', which is understood here as manifestation or revelation. If man
is the manifestation of God, then man cannot veil what God has revealed. Woman
should be veiled, for she is the glory not of God but of man. But in what sense
is she the glory of man, and what has that to do with her veiling herself? If
man is the image and glory of God in the sense that he is the revelation of
God, is woman the glory of man as the revelation of man? That seems unlikely:
for, unlike God, man is not hidden and does not need a manifestation external
to himself. Even if he did, why would it need to be concealed behind a veil?
The
moment of theological substance here is concealed within a semantic slippage
between the two occurrences of doxa. Man is the glory of God as the
manifestation of God which should not be veiled; yet woman is veiled not as the
manifestation of man but as ‘the glory of man' in a rather different sense. In
1 Thessalonians 2.20 Paul writes: ‘You are our glory and our joy [he doxa
hemon kai he chara]'. In Philippians 3.19 it is said of certain persons
that ‘their glory is in their shame [he doxa en te aischune auton\ \ In
one case the object of glory is an appropriate one, in the other it is
inappropriate - but in both cases doxa is the object of a person's joy,
love and devotion. This sense of doxa makes 1 Corinthians 11.7
comprehensible: man as the manifestation of God should not be veiled, but
woman as the object of man's erotic joy, love and devotion should be veiled.
Why? Because it is her face that is the focal point for the male erotic drive,
which - contrary to our earlier, more negative impression - may intend to
honour her and may be gladly reciprocated in the mutuality to which eros
aspires, but which has no place within the agape at the heart of the
congregation's being and life. This human attraction to the glory of the other
is real enough, and the congregation will have to accommodate it and will not
wish simply to deny it. But, as a sign that the togetherness of man and woman
'in the Lord' is not the togetherness of eros, it is appropriate that the glory
should lie concealed behind a veil. The Pauline veil invites theological
reflection not on the problem of a 'hierarchical' ordering of the sexes and the
possibility of an 'egalitarian' alternative, but on the difference between
agape and eros as the basis for the togetherness of man and woman in Christ.[xxiii]
For
man is not from woman but woman from man; and man was not created for woman but
woman for man
(vv. 8-9). Within a few sentences, this asymmetrical and irreversible
relationship — man is not from woman but woman from man — will be reversed and
symmetry will be restored: as woman is from man, so too man is through woman
(v. 12). If the relationship of origin is reversible, so too is the
teleological relationship. As woman is for man, so too man is for woman. The
order, in which one is irreversibly from and for the other, is precarious and
can only be maintained as a fleeting moment within a larger picture of male
and female togetherness 'in the Lord' (v. 11). Yet, for a moment, this
abstraction does occur, and the order is asserted. The intention is to
substantiate the claim that 'woman is the glory of man' and should therefore
veil herself.
Why is woman the
glory of man, the object of his erotic joy, love and devotion? It is because
'it is not good for the man [ha-adam] to be alone' (Gen. 2.18). 'Adam' is
'man', and if solitude is not good for the first man then it is not good for
man as such. Man is 'not without woman' (1 Cor. 11.11). Although the creator
looks on all of his works and pronounces them to be 'good', in the case of the
solitary man formed from the dust of the ground he acknowledges that his work
is ‘not good’ — not good, that is, in itself and in its abstraction and its
solitude. Solitary man, this being that in its abstraction and self-containment
is ‘not good’, needs a helper that even God cannot be: a helper kenegdo,
who corresponds to him and is his counterpart, like him but also different and
therefore not a mere repetition of the same, let alone an inferior imitation.
Pure likeness would be a repetition that would merely replicate the original
solitude. Pure difference would leave man and the other separated by an abyss
of mutual incomprehension, and solitude would remain unbroken. Although the
creation of the animals establishes a relative rather than an absolute
difference, in which some elements of likeness remain and therefore some
possibility of mutuality, it is mentioned only to highlight the distinctiveness
of the ‘helper corresponding to him’, in whom difference and likeness must be
equally original.[xxiv]
The creation of the
counterpart from out of man’s own flesh and bone signifies not inferiority — an
inferior helper would be another animal, not a counterpart — but the
co-presence in this other of likeness and difference. It is in this sense that
woman is created ‘from’ and ‘for’ man: not as a sign of secondariness and
inferiority but so that her being can make good a being that is ‘not good’
without her. The Pauline language and the Genesis narrative are ‘androcentric’
in the sense that woman’s being is determined by the being of the man; her
existence rectifies the deficiencies of his, and nothing is said of the meaning
of her existence in itself and apart from his. Yet his own existence in itself
and apart from her has been described as ‘not good’. If man-in-himself is an
abstraction contrary to the will of the creator and the nature of the creature,
then he hardly constitutes a ‘centre’ in relation to which woman’s existence
is peripheral and dependent. If she is dependent on him, then he is also
dependent on her if his being is to display the goodness proper to the creature
rather than languishing in the impossible limbo of the not-good. She is the
helper he needs to draw him out of this limbo. Her help is not a help that he
could in the last resort do without; unlike the help of the animals, it is
essential to his being. If he stands at the centre of God's creation, he does
not do so without her.
The
second creation story substantiates the Pauline claim that ‘woman is not apart
from man nor man from woman' (i Cor. ii.ii),
but it also substantiates his claim that there is an order in this
relationship. Man is not from woman but woman from man; man was not created for
woman but woman for man. This is an androcentrism that draws woman into the
centre to share that centre with man — but for man's sake (di' anthropon),
so that his existence may be good rather than not- good. When woman is
brought to man, she does not address him, naming him and identifying him in
relation to her own being and its needs. It is he who speaks — speaking of
her in the third person rather than addressing her directly, and finding in her
being from his own bones and flesh a relationship of likeness and derivation
that must be mirrored in the medium of language: woman is from man and is
therefore called ishshah, which is from ish. But this act of
naming is not like the naming of the animals that the man had earlier carried
out, in accordance with the divine will. Here, the naming stems from an
ecstatic moment of recognition: ‘This at last is bone of my bones and flesh of
my flesh . . .' (Gen. 2.23). In this other he recognizes the counterpart, like
him in her difference from him and different in her likeness to him. The
likeness arises from the intimacy of an original physical identity of bone and
flesh, and it is this likeness within the medium of otherness that is expressed
in the event in which man and woman become ‘one flesh', naked yet unashamed
despite the absence of the veil (vv. 24—5). The recognition of the helper and
counterpart reaches its goal in physical union; and it constitutes woman as
‘the glory of man'.15
15 According to Gunkel, this passage is
'the prototypical example of an aetiological myth . . . The question here is,
“How is it that man strives for union with woman?'' The myth answers, “Man
desires to become one flesh with woman because he was originally one flesh with
her''. In love that which was originally one is reunited . . . The nature of
the love [the narrator] intends is very clear from the expressions he uses: it
is sexual union' (Genesis, i3). While it is true that the narrative is
concerned
In the
Genesis narrative and its Pauline interpretation, eros is construed
asymmetrically as the movement of man towards woman, arising out of the moment
of recognition and culminating in the union of flesh — the movement in which
‘a man leaves his father and his mother and cleaves to his wife . . . ’ (v.
24). That is not to say that in eros the male is merely ‘active’ and the female
merely ‘passive’. Male activity over against female passivity would be
difference without likeness, difference hardened into opposition, and it is not
this that the erotic moment of recognition intends — except when it takes the
pathological form of the gaze to which Susanna is subjected. The recognition of
the counterpart seeks an answering recognition. The asymmetry of eros, as
rendered in these texts, is one of initiative and response. Yet there seems to
be no compelling reason for this asymmetry, outside the constraints of cultural
assumptions. Thus, in contrast, the erotic dialogue of the Song of Solomon is
evenly distributed between the male and the female speakers, and the initiative
passes from one to the other. On occasion she can acknowledge his initiative as
calling for her response: ‘My beloved speaks and says to me: Arise my love, my
fair one, and come away. . . ’ (Cant. 2.10). But she too may claim the
initiative, even if she fails to attain her object: ‘Upon my bed by night I
sought him whom my soul loves; I sought him but found him not, I called him but
he gave no answer’ (3.1). Indeed, within this enclosed world of eros the idea
of‘initiative’ is purely relative and may drop out of view. If ‘my beloved is
mine and I am his’, then ‘initiative’ is subsumed and dissolved into mutual
belonging. The partners see themselves as responding to an initiative not of
the other but of eros itself, and as subject to an ethical imperative to allow
this to be so. Thus, the ‘daughters of Jerusalem’ are twice adjured ‘that you
stir not up nor awaken love until it please’ (3.5, 8.4). Sexual initiative may
result in the form of love without the reality. Mechanically, the partners go
through the motions of love; but the reality is absent not because the woman
has taken the initiative rather
with 'the creation of humankind which reaches its
goal in the complementary society of man and woman’, it is implausible to rule
out a concern with 'the origin of the mutual attraction of the sexes’, as
Westermann does (Genesis 1—11, 232). than the man but because both
partners have failed to subject themselves to the initiative of love itself.
When they speak of love as strong as death and claim that many waters cannot
quench it (8.6—7), they are speaking not primarily of themselves but of the
suprapersonal quasi-divine power that holds them in its grasp and demands their
obedience. In this world, the lovers’ language shows that as woman is the glory
of man so man is the glory of woman.
Paul,
however, is dependent on the Genesis model of eros in terms of male initiative
and female response. (If this model is inadequate, as it is, it is no more so
than the erotic fantasy of absolute and unbroken mutuality within an enclosed
garden cut off from the external world.)16 Woman
is the glory of man, but man is the glory not of woman but of God; it must
therefore be woman’s face that is concealed behind a veil if eros is to be
restrained from penetrating the internal life of the community, insinuating
itself into the agape that binds the congregation together and secretly
subverting it. Woman’s veil ensures that the male gaze will not find its
object. Yet eros is not simply cast out. A barrier is placed in its way to
prevent its extending itself beyond its limits, but its right to existence
within its limits is not denied. To identify woman as the glory of man is to
acknowledge not only the reality but also the validity of the erotic look of
recognition. Nor is this merely the pragmatic concession of one whose real
belief is that ‘it is good for a man not to touch a woman’ (1 Cor. 7.1).
Pragmatism can speak of‘conjugal rights’, ‘self-control’ and ‘passion’ (7.3, 5,
9, 36), but it will not speak of ‘glory’ or of an original eros that is older
even than original sin and that still participates in the goodness of the hrst
creation. Within the limit marked by the veil, the eros that unites man and
woman as one flesh is good, and its exclusion from the agape that unites the
congregation as one body is not a rejection or a denial. To mark a limit is not
to deny. The importance of
16 Phyllis Trible’s comments exemplify
the modern tendency to idealize the lovers of the Song of Songs: 'Their love is
truly bone of bone and flesh of flesh, and this image of God male and female is
indeed very good . . . Testifying to the goodness of creation, then, eroticism
becomes worship in the context of grace . . . In this setting, there is no male
dominance, no female subordination, and no stereotyping of either sex’ (God
and the Rhetoric of Sexuality, Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1978, 161). this
distinction comes to light if the Genesis narrative is set alongside an
alternative account of the origins of man and woman.
According
to Plato's Timaeus, the goodness of the world's divine maker guarantees
that, so far as possible, the world too will be good.[xxv] Desiring to reduce the disorder of the primitive
chaos to order, he implanted in it soul and intelligence, the principle of
orderly temporal movement manifested supremely in the heavens that makes them
‘a moving image of eternity' — the timeless world of the ideas that the maker
used as his pattern (370). The ®rst of the gods is the earth herself, but other
gods are created out of lire and entrusted with the task of making the
remaining creatures; immortal seed is given to them in order that they may
blend it with what is mortal. This seed is composed of soul, which the maker
divided up into as many souls as there are stars, allocating each soul to its
star. ‘And setting them as if in a chariot, he showed them the nature of the universe
[ton tou pantos phusin] and told them the laws of their destiny — how
the ®rst birth [genesis protO] would be one and the same for all, so
that no-one might be unfairly treated by him; and how each would be sown in its
appropriate instrument of time and be born as the most god-fearing of living
things; and how, since human nature is twofold [diples ouses tes anthropines
phuseos] the superior sex [to kreitton genos] was that which would
be called “man”. And when, by necessity [ex anagkes], they should be
implanted in bodies, subject to physical gain and loss, they would all
inevitably be endowed, ®rst, with a common faculty of sensation [aestheosis],
dependent on external stimulation; second, with desire [eroota] mingled
with pain and pleasure; and, in addition, with fear and anger and their
accompanying feelings, and also with their opposites. If they mastered these,
they would live justly, but if they were mastered by them, wickedly. And the
one who lived well for his appointed time of life would return home to his
native star and live an appropriately happy life; but anyone who failed to do
so would be changed into woman’s nature at the second birth [eis gunaikos
phusin en to deutera genesei metaboloi]. And if in this form too he
continued to do wrong, he would be changed into some animal suitable to his
particular kind of wrongdoing . . . After the sowing, he gave to the newly made
gods the task of forming mortal bodies, and of framing whatever of the human
soul still needed to be added, with whatever pertained to it, and of governing
the mortal creature in the best way possible — so long as it did not become a
cause of evil to itself’ (41E—42E). These instructions were duly carried out,
and the human frame was constructed — the prototype that would in subsequent
generations be transformed in a descending scale into ‘women and other
animals’ (76E). In due course, ‘the men of the ®rst generation [ton
genomenon andron] who were cowardly or passed their lives in wrongdoing
were . . . transformed into women at their second birth [en te deutera
genesei]. So that was when the gods created sexual love [ton tes
xunousias erota] . . . ’ (90E—91A). In the male, a modi®cation to the
urinary tract enabled it to serve also as a means of generation. ‘Thus in men
the nature of the genital organs is to be disobedient and self-willed [autok-
rateos], like a creature deaf to reason [anupoekoon tou logou],
attempting to dominate all because of its frenzied desires’ (91B). In the
female, the gods provided ‘a living creature within them which longs to bear
children’ (91c). The mutual distress of male and female is assuaged only when
‘the mutual desire and love [he epithumia kai ho eros] unites them, and,
as if picking fruit from a tree, they sow the ploughland of the womb with germs
of life, unformed and too small to see, which take shape and grow big within;
after which they bring them forth into the light and complete the generation of
the living creature’ (91c—d).
As in
Genesis, man is formed ®rst and then woman. But in Genesis, woman is formed in
order to remedy the not-goodness of man’s solitary state; in the Timaeus,
she incarnates the not- goodness of his moral choices, so that — as in the
Pandora myth — her being is his punishment.[xxvi] The plunging of the soul into the chaos of matter
subjects it to a disorder that it can and must overcome through the practice of
virtue and philosophy. The original all-male generation face a difficult task
as they struggle to come to terms with their incarceration in the body ±
although their task is not impossible and they can rely on the help of the gods
and of the godlike principle within themselves. Yet a gradual decay from
generation to generation is inevitable, and its first manifestation is the
woman who is, as it were, designed around the modi®ed male bodily parts that
are now to serve as organs of generation, and who mirrors their irrational
behaviour. The erotic union of man and woman engulfs them in the disorder of
passion, and, like woman’s very existence, is an unfortunate side-effect of the
original male’s lapse from virtue and philosophy.
At the beginning of
the Timaeus, Socrates summarizes the previous day’s discussion in which
he had outlined his ideal state. He had spoken then of the role of women,
arguing that so far as possible the differences between men and women should be
erased: ‘Their natures were to be harmonized with the men’s, and all
occupations, both in war and in the rest of life, were to be common [koina]
to all’ (18c). The assumption here that woman is capable of the life of virtue
is in tension with the later claim that she is the ®rst step in man’s downward
path that leads beyond her into the existences of birds, mammals, reptiles and
®sh. Might there have been a quite different Platonic myth of origins that assigned
to woman a position of equality rather than inferiority? The problem is that,
in contrast to Genesis, the cosmology within which man and woman come into
being is for Plato already gendered. The world is a visible and changing copy
of an intelligible and unchanging pattern, and as such it is the product of two
principles, intelligence and necessity. The necessity that is both the medium
for the expression of intelligence and its limit is described as the
‘receptacle, as it were the nurse, of all becoming’ [pases geneseos
hupodochen auto, hoion tithenen] (49a), about which it is hard to speak
accurately because its unstable elements (earth, air, ®re and water) undergo
constant transformations. ‘Having no stability, they elude the designation
“this” or “that” or any other term that expresses permanence’ (49E).[xxvii] The receptacle ‘is established by nature as raw
material for everything, formed and shaped by the hgures that pass into it, so
that it appears different at different times. And the things which pass into
and out of it are copies of the eternal realities [ton onton aei mimemata],
receiving their stamp in a way hard to describe ... It is appropriate to
describe that which receives [to dechomenon] as the Mother, the
originating model [to hothen] as the Father, and the nature they produce
between them as the Offspring’ (50c-d).
Because of her shifting, unstable and impermanent character, ‘the mother and
receptacle of all sensible things’ - the matter out of which, on their maternal
side, they are constituted - is not to be identihed with any individual
elements or compounds but can only be described as ‘invisible and formless,
all-receptive [pan- deches], partaking in the intelligible [tou
noetou] in a way that is perplexing and very hard to grasp’ (51A—b). The receptacle is also the
‘ever-existing space’ (52B) within which all things come to be, and in its
pure, primeval form as ‘the nurse of becoming’ it lacks even the relative
stability of the sensible world of our experience, since its contents are in
constant process of movement and separation. Thus the world is a kind of
compromise between a paternal principle of intelligence and order and a
maternal/material principle of necessity and disorder. In a world so
constituted, the being of woman must be a step downward from the being
of man into the irrational chaos; for the chaos is itself woman, the womb of
becoming. The hrst generation of men is poised precariously between the starry
heights of paternal intelligence and the irrational maternal abyss.[xxviii]
That is
also essentially the situation of the present generation of men — the men of
whom and to whom Plato speaks. In the Symposium, Pausanias (the second
speaker) distinguishes between two goddesses of love, and this distinction is
foundational for Socrates’s final unveiling of the ‘truth’ of eros (which takes
the form of a reported speech by a woman, Diotima, who is perhaps assigned her
revelatory role in preference to a man partly as the embodiment of philosophia,
partly in order to rule out the possible complication of an erotic relationship
between Socrates and the revealer). According to Pausanias, Phaedrus (the first
speaker) has made the mistake of assuming that love is single. Although he has
spoken primarily of the love of men and boys, he has claimed that women too may
demonstrate love’s willingness to sacrifice itself for the sake of the beloved.
Alcestis’ love for her husband has been placed in the same category as
Achilles’ love for Patroclus. Phaedrus has failed to identify precisely what the
eros is in whose praise he has agreed to speak. ‘If there were a single
Aphrodite there would be a single Eros, but since there are two of her there
must also be two Eroses [duo Erote]. How can anyone doubt that the
goddess is double? One is the elder, the motherless daughter of Ouranos, whom
we call Aphrodite the heavenly [Ouranian]. The other is younger, the
child of Zeus and Dione, and is called Aphrodite the common [Pandemos].
It follows that the Eros which is the partner of the latter should be called common
Eros and the other heavenly Eros’ (i8od
— e). The devotees of common Eros
are ‘the meaner sort of men’, who ‘first of all love women as well as boys;
second, they love the body rather than the soul; third, they choose the most
ignorant objects, looking only to the gratification of desire . . . This love
is from the goddess, far the younger of the two, who partakes in her origin of
both male and female. But the love which is from the heavenly Aphrodite
partakes not of the female but only of the male — and this is the love of boys
[ho ton paidon eros]; also, being the elder, she is free from
wantonness. And so those who are inspired by this love are attracted towards
the male sex as being by nature the stronger
strife’’ began’ (461). The coherent metaphysical
context of the account in the Timaeus suggests that any 'playful’
elements here should be taken seriously. and more intelligent’ (i8ib—c). The heavenly love of man and
boy is older than the common love of man and woman: and this claim may be read
back into the Timaeus. Heavenly male Eros is original, and may be traced
back to the ®rst generation of men. That is the meaning of the ancient myth of
an Aphrodite who originates purely from the male. In contrast, heterosexual
Eros is degenerate and secondary, deriving from that younger, fallen world in
which genitality and woman represent the victory of the primal Mother over the
primal Father in the struggle for the ®rst men’s allegiance. The homoerotic
relationship should exclude genitality because genitality is essentially
feminine; the purity of Aphrodite Ourania is corrupted by the intrusion of
feminized bodily parts which in their chaotic resistance to rational control
represent in the male person the downward pull of the Mother. Aphrodite
Pandemos is passion, and passion
21
is
a woman.[xxix]
The eros of man and
woman has no place at the symposium’s celebration of eros. It belongs to the
feminine sphere of the passions and pleasures, which it is philosophy’s
vocation to combat.[xxx] In the Platonic dialogue, philosophy strives to recreate
the all-male society of the ®rst generation. (Thus, on the day of Socrates'
death, Xanthippe must be sent home before the ®nal dialogue can get under way (Phaedo,
6oa).) In contrast, in the
Pauline text ‘woman is the glory of man’. She is created from and for man, but
her secondariness is not that of the inferior whose being represents the
decline from original perfection towards the maternal abyss, but that of the
counterpart whose being contradicts and overcomes the imperfection of an
original being that is not-good in its abstract solitude. In her, that original
being ®nds its telos. But that means that the male does not here
represent the pure original moment. Woman too belongs to the moment of origin,
and in the erotic union of man and woman as one flesh that moment of origin is
still present, however distorted its empirical expression. The eros of man and
woman is given space within the world — a demythologized space in which the
archaic myth of a world that arises from the conjunction of male and female
principles has been supplanted by the ungendered relation of the creator ex
nihilo to the creature.
Eros is given space
within the world, but it is a limited space. Within the new creation, it no
longer belongs at the centre of the relationship of man to woman. At this
centre is now the community of those who are in Christ, in which the
relationship of man and woman reflects the pattern of Christ’s agape. The word
of the Lord which founds this community is proclaimed by women as well as by
men, and they too articulate the community’s answering word. As a sign of the
new limit assigned to eros, a veil is interposed between the woman who prays
and prophesies and the men to and for whom she speaks. Otherwise (Paul
believes), her voice may not be heard. For the sake of the word of God, the
glory of man must be concealed.
THE AUTHORITY OF THE VEIL [VERSES 10 ± 16)
For
this reason the woman should have authority on her head, because of the angels (v. 10). ‘For this
reason . . . ’ - because woman is the glory of man, created from and for man;
but also, ‘because of the angels’. Yet the veil is not the sign that
woman is the glory of man. On the contrary, it is the sign that, ‘in the Lord’,
the limitations of this status are overcome. As the glory of man, woman
responds to a prior male initiative. In the Lord, as she prophesies and prays
on behalf of the congregation, she represents both God’s initiative and the
human response; and she can do so because in this case the pattern of initiative
and response is no longer gendered. Conceivably, it might be otherwise. The
divine initiative might be represented by the male prophet, the human response
by the praying woman; or men might lay claim to both the ‘masculine’ and the
‘feminine’ roles, thereby asserting the deity’s special affinity to the male.
In reality, however, both the divine initiative and the human response are
embodied in the figure ofJesus who, as the agent of the new creation, creates
anew and does not simply underwrite the gender roles inscribed in the old
creation or in the cultures built on that foundation. ‘Old things [ta archaia]
have passed away - behold, new things [kaina] have come!’ (2 Cor. 5.17).
In the sphere of the new creation, the vanishing archaia include the
male erotic gaze as the centre and foundation of the relation of men and women.
Negatively, the veil is the sign of this decentering of the old. Positively, it
is the sign of the new reality in which ‘your sons and your daughters shall
prophesy’ because the Spirit has been poured out on all flesh (Joel 2.28, Acts
2.17). The veil is ‘authority’ (exousia) on the head of the woman who
prophesies because it declares and enacts the passing away of the old and the
dawning of the 23 new.
The sign
of the new exousia is needed not only because, in the created order,
'woman is the glory of man' but also 'because of the angels'. Are these the
'sons of God' who, according to Genesis 6.2, 'saw that the daughters of men
were fair, and took to wife such of them as they chose'? Or are they the
angelic guardians of the created order? There is perhaps no need to choose
between these two interpretations. The angels are 'guardians and stewards',
they are 'the elemental spirits of the universe' (ta stoicheia tou kosmou)
to whom God has entrusted the administration of the world until the 'fulness of
time' and the sending of his Son; but those who have received the Spirit of
God's Son are no longer the slaves of these 'weak and impoverished' beings
(Gal. 4.1-9). The angels are 'the rulers of this age, who are passing away' (1
Cor. 2.6). Appointed by God, it is not yet clear how far they were faithful to
their stewardship; that will only be known on the day when 'we shall judge
angels' (6.3). These angels or stoicheia are the foundations of the old
order, the shadowy powers that stand behind and guarantee the visible powers
operative in the human and the natural realms. If the male erotic drive towards
the female is one of those visible powers, it is imaginable that we also
encounter here the quasitranscendence of a non-divine being that is
nevertheless, from the standpoint of the old order, suprahuman. Eros is not a
god, but its pseudo-divinity is easily mistaken for actual divinity: that is
perhaps the significance of the old legend of the angels' unions with human
women and of the similar tales told among the Greeks.
The woman prophet does not cower
behind her veil, fearful of attracting the angels' erotic attentions. The
Pauline attitude 23 That
exousia in 1 Cor. 11.10 must refer to the woman's authority, and not to
her subordination to male authority, was shown by Morna Hooker in an article
dating from 1964 (reprinted in From Adam to Christ: Essays on Paul,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990, 113 — 20). 'The head-covering
which symbolizes the effacement of man's glory in the presence of God also
serves as the sign of the exousia which is given to the woman; with the
glory of man hidden she, too, may reflect the glory of God. Far from being a
symbol of the woman's subjection to man, therefore, her head-covering is what
Paul calls it — authority: in prayer and prophecy she, like the man, is under
the authority of God' (119 — 20). to these beings is more contempt than fear. The
veil is a prophetic sign to the angels that the new creation has dawned and
that their jurisdiction has passed away. They may be named impressively as
‘thrones and lordships, rules and authorities [archai, exousiai]’ (Col.
1.16), but the exousia of the woman prophet, represented by the veil, is
greater than theirs; for if anyone (man or woman) is in Christ, there is new
creation (2 Cor. 5.17), and that is what the veil proclaims. The archai
belong to the archaia that are passing away. Christ has freed us from
their dominion; he has demythologized them.
But
neither is woman apart from man nor man apart from woman, in the Lord (v. 11). Woman must
have authority on her head because, from the standpoint of the hrst creation,
she is the glory of man and because, from the standpoint of the new creation,
her being is no longer limited by this original identity. Yet, in its negative
and positive aspects, the veil is a complex symbol that will easily be
misunderstood. A disclaimer is therefore necessary. In decentering eros in the
name of the agape of the new creation, the veil introduces a physical barrier
between man and woman. Her voice can still be heard, but her face is concealed
behind a blank screen. The veil will all too easily solidify into a symbol of a
division in which man and woman are apart from one another: and Paul perhaps
writes his disclaimer precisely in order to pre-empt this obvious objection
from a sceptical Corinthian readership.
The disclaimer is
all too necessary, for the danger of misunderstanding is real. In this very
passage, Paul himself has come perilously close to losing sight of his true
theme - the oneness of man and woman in Christ. If in the old creation woman is
the glory of man (v. 7), how is it that, even in the new creation, man is still
the head of woman (v. 3)? Is the new merely a repetition of the old? Why is the
language of‘new’ and ‘old’ not used here, and why is there no explicit
affirmation and celebration of woman’s prophetic ministry and of the pouring
out of the Spirit on all flesh? Why is the meaning of the veil as a sign of
authority over the powers merely hinted at? Throughout the passage, we
recognize genuine theological concerns that belong at the heart of Paul’s
gospel. But they lie beneath the surface of his text; he does not himself
identify them clearly enough, and his language betrays uncertainty and anxiety.
The disclaimer — in the Lord woman and man are together, not apart — is
addressed in part to himself. Yet our concern is not with the text in relation
to its author, but with the theological issue of the standing of woman and man
‘in the Lord’ that we must articulate with the help of his text.
What would happen if
the veil became a symbol of division between man and woman? What would happen
is what does happen a few chapters later, where a later editor has inserted the
fateful words: ‘As in all the churches of the saints, the women should keep
silence in the churches. For they are not permitted to speak, but should be
subordinate, as even the law says. If there is anything they desire to know,
let them ask their husbands at home. For it is shameful for a woman to speak in
church’ (1 Cor. 14-33b—35). Even here, the separation of man and woman is not
absolute. Women are silent in church, it is only men who speak, but women are
still physically present. Through the Spirit, their silent listening and their
asking questions at home will not be in vain. But although elements of the
togetherness of man and woman in the Lord survive even here, the theological
loss is disastrous. The barrier between those who speak and those who are
silent makes it possible for men to dehne themselves apart from women and for
women to dehne themselves apart from men. First the veil makes woman invisible,
and then a further instruction makes her inaudible too.[xxxi]
Traces
of the distorted self-definitions that result from this hardening of the veil
into a dividing-wall may be found in the pastoral epistles. Once again, silence
and submissiveness is required of women in the most emphatic terms (1 Tim. 2.11
— 12), on the grounds that ‘Adam was formed first, then Eve; and Adam was not
deceived, but the woman was deceived and became a transgressor. Yet she shall
be saved through childbearing . . . ’ (vv. 13—15). As Adam is Man, so Eve is
Woman. Revealing in her conduct the general untrustworthiness of womankind, Eve
disqualifies all her daughters from exercising authority in the church. Man may
exercise that authority because he is Adam, who was not deceived. Man is first,
Woman is second; he is to lead, she must follow. So inferior is her status that
she can normally be ignored. So superior is his status that he can identify
himself and his perspective as the norm and the truth, without reference to
her. Disillusioned by Eve's untrustworthiness, Adam leaves her to her
child-bearing and goes out to create a world or a church in his own image. He
does not entirely succeed. He cannot escape the togetherness of man and woman,
in the first creation or in the Lord. But his self-de®nitions apart from woman
are not without damaging effect.
Silenced
within the public space of the church, woman is banished to the private space
of the home. There she is still permitted to ask questions, and there she may
choose to construct her own self-de®nitions, apart from man. The author of 2
Timothy knows of certain men who ‘make their way into homes and capture little
women [gunaikaria], overwhelmed by their sins and swayed by various
desires, always eager to learn but incapable of reaching a knowledge of the
truth' (2 Tim. 3.6—7). Under firm paternal authority in church, women have
greater freedom at home. There are men who are prepared to treat women as
thinking people and not just as child-rearers, and women can choose to admit
them into their homes, assessing what they have to say in complete
independence from the
suggests a deutero-Pauline origin. These are
strong points, although not absolutely decisive. But even if Paul did write 1
Cor. 14.34—5, a passage so at odds with its immediate and broader contexts can
be regarded as an unfortunate aberration. truth handed down in the
church. Excluded from the church’s all-male teaching ministry, women react by
thinking independently at home. In reaction against their exclusion, they
dehne themselves as Outsiders. The author may perhaps have been right to
complain that such people ‘turn away from listening to the truth and wander
into myths’ (4.4). But he has failed to notice his own responsibility for their
decision to dehne themselves in terms of these myths and to reject ecclesial
truth; for it is he who has decreed that men are the only reliable mouthpieces
of ecclesial truth and that women’s calling is to submit in silence. Where man
dehnes himself apart from woman, then woman will dehne herself over against
man. Even in the pastoral epistles, that is not the whole truth of the relation
of man and woman in the Lord. The church leader is to treat older women like
mothers, younger women like sisters, without using his authority as a pretext
for harshness or sexual exploitation (1 Tim. 5.2). Widows are to be honoured
for their life of prayer, and where appropriate the church is to give them
hnancial support (5.3—8). Timothy’s own acquaintance with holy scripture seems
to derive from the teaching he received in childhood from his mother Lois and
his grandmother Eunice (2 Tim. 3.15, 1.5). The author’s frequently expressed
concern for decency and respectability in family life is not necessarily
misplaced. Yet, although vestiges of the truth that man and woman are together
in the Lord survive even here, the impact of distorted self-dehnitions in which
man and woman hold themselves apart from one another is palpable.[xxxii]
Paul’s disclaimer —
that in the Lord woman is not woman apart from man and man is not man apart
from woman — is all too necessary. But its function is not only to answer the
objection that the effect of the veil will be to separate men and women; it is
also a positive affirmation. In itself, it lacks dehnition. All kinds of more
or less satisfactory social and ecclesial arrangements might claim to
represent the togetherness of man and woman in the Lord. It is the context that
gives this affirmation the clarity and the critical edge it might seem to lack
as a general principle. Clarity and critical edge are still lacking where this
text is understood as a general affirmation of the ‘equality’ of man and woman,
over against the ‘hierarchical’ language of the preceding verses. Like
‘togetherness’, ‘equality’ begs a number of questions. What sort of equality?
What forms will it take, and why? In itself, the notion of a ‘discipleship of
equals’ is purely negative and polemical, and has nothing to say about the
nature, form and basis of this equality except that it excludes every kind of
inequality. The Pauline text is best understood on the basis of its own
polarity of togetherness and apartness, within a broader context marked by the
symbol of the veil.
The togetherness
which this text articulates is a togetherness of speech — the
distinctively Christian speech of proclamation and prayer. This speech is the
speech of men, and it is the speech of women. The veil that differentiates them
is intended to preserve the distinctively Christian character of this speech as
the dialogue of God and the community, by screening out the erotic look — the
irrelevant and impertinent intrusion of the old creation, in which woman is the
glory of man, into the new creation in which the Spirit is poured out upon all
flesh. The togetherness of man and woman will not be the primary content of
this speech. The divine word and the thankful human response refer to the event
in which ‘God was in Christ reconciling the world to himself’ (2 Cor. 5.19).
That alone is their foundation and content, and it can never be replaced by any
other. ‘No other foundation can anyone lay than that which is laid, which is Jesus
Christ’ (1 Cor. 3.11). ‘I decided to know nothing among you except Jesus Christ
and him crucified’ (1 Cor. 2.2): Paul’s proclamation is the paradigm for the
prophet’s. It is true that the reconciliation of the world through the
crucified Christ entails a social embodiment in which there is reconciliation
between humans —Jew and Greek, slave and free, male and female. But the divine
reconciliation of the world cannot be reduced to this social embodiment.
In the speech that enacts the dialogue between God and the community, the
community is not simply speaking about itself. Responsibility for this speech
is shared between men and women, and this shared responsibility relates more
immediately to the form of the speech than to its content.
What takes place when,
in the midst of the congregation, man or woman speaks in proclamation or
prayer? In the ®rst instance, woman (or man) makes the divine-human speech at
the heart of Christian and ecclesial existence her own speech. She assumes
responsibility towards it. This is always a shared responsibility. Even
as one who speaks, she must continue to listen to others' speech; for her
speech is not hers alone but the speech of God to the community and of the
community to God, and the word of God and of the community is not exhausted by
her word. Her word is subordinated to that general word ± the old word that has
already been spoken and heard, sedimented in the form of a tradition, and the
new word that now comes to expression on the basis of the old. If the tradition
is living and not dead, it is always in need of new articulation, and the new
word is therefore not an impersonal repetition of a static tradition but an
ever-new event. It is not a word-in-general that comes to expression through
her voice and mouth; it is genuinely her word, no less her own for
being a contemporary articulation of the living word of tradition. Yet a word
that was exclusively her own would be incomprehensible to its hearers,
an instance of the pure glossolalia whose tendency to exclude its
hearers from participation will later be criticized (1 Cor. 14.1 — 19). In
taking responsibility for the word in which God speaks to the community and the
community speaks to God, the woman who prophesies and prays makes the word her
own.
In speaking rather
than remaining silent, the one who prays or prophesies refuses the temptation
to withdraw from responsibility and to leave that responsibility to others. If
he or she leaves the speaking to others, speaking and hearing will both be
impaired as speakers and hearers are divided from each other. Where speech is
met by silence, it fails to attain its object — even if the silence is the
silence of attentive listening rather than that of indifference. Speech seeks
to evoke speech; communication intends dialogue, as the circular movement of
the divine speech and the human response indicates in paradigmatic form. Where
speech is met by unbroken silence, the speaker is not heard but overheard
talking to himself. There is no response, and no further impartation to others.
The responsibility of speech may indeed be assumed in various ways, outside as
well as inside the formal meetings of the community for worship. Even though
she is not permitted to teach or have authority over men, Timothy's mother
proclaims the word of the Lord to her young son and articulates on his behalf
the prayer that answers it. Nevertheless, the circular movement of authentic
Christian speech will be impaired if, in communal worship, an absolute
distinction is drawn between those who speak and those who either remain silent
or who speak only in the impersonal language of the ®rst person plural.
The one who assumes
the responsibility of speech does so in the presence of others. Her
appropriation of speech is a public act, and the movement out of silence into
speech is a venture that exposes her to risk. She undertakes this movement
because she is called to do so through the Spirit, who bestows on each the charisma
that is to be used for the common good. It is the Spirit who opens her mouth and
gives her utterance and who ensures that, however it is received, that
utterance is not in vain. Since utterance is undertaken for others' sake, it is
grounded in the agape that desires the true well-being of the other ± her own
love for the other insofar as it arises out of the divine agape that is the
content of her proclamation and her thanksgiving. But she participates in the
divine agape through the mediation of the congregation, whose true life, apart
from all accidents and distortions, is the life of agape. The love for the
other that impels her to speak is a love that has ®rst comprehended her in its
scope ± a human love that is also a divine love, not partly human and partly
divine but wholly human and wholly divine, the one because it is also the
other: for, without compromising the distinction between divine and human,
‘divine' here refers to a reality that is turned towards humanity rather than
enclosed in itself, and ‘human' refers to a reality that is not left in its own
self-enclosure but drawn into the koinonia of the divine agape.
In the Lord, man and
woman are together and not apart because they participate alike in the
divine-human agape. But their togetherness should also be manifested in a
shared responsibility for speech. Within the meeting of the congregation,
women as well as men must articulate the distinctive Christian word in its
circular, dialogical form. This ‘must’ does not simply reflect the fact that
the Spirit happens to bestow his gifts indifferently on both men and women. Nor
is it the case that a woman must speak so as to enable other women to
‘identify’ with her, as male listeners ‘identify’ with a man who speaks. That
would be division, not togetherness. The man who speaks is not
man-in-abstraction, and the woman who speaks is not woman-in-abstraction — man
or woman turned away from the other and addressing his or her own kind. The one
who speaks is the man who is not apart from woman or the woman who is not apart
from man. If man alone speaks, he will represent only the abstraction of a man
who is apart from woman, an absolutized and distorted maleness. Woman must
speak as well as man so that the divine-human discourse at the heart of the
church’s life may be represented and enacted not by an abstraction but by a
full and genuine humanity — full and genuine in both man and woman when each is
not apart from the other. Here too, it is ‘not good for the man to be alone’.
However ambiguously
and questionably, the Pauline veil intends to preserve this koinonia in
Christian utterance rather than undermining it. Inappropriate in practice, it
retains its symbolic theological significance. Woman is to speak from behind a
veil in order that the agape that is the motivation and the content of her
speech should reach its intended goal and not be turned aside by an intrusion
from the old order. It is a sign that the mythologized, quasi-transcendent
authority of eros is excluded from the koinonia of agape, since it intends the
possession of the other in the form of bodily union rather than the other’s
divinely determined well-being. The erotic koinonia of man and woman is — we
might almost say — a parody of the true koinonia of man and woman in the Lord.
For
as woman is from man, so too man is through woman ... (v. 12). Following his
affirmation of the togetherness of man and woman in the Lord, Paul unexpectedly
reverts to the sphere of creation in order to support this affirmation. ‘Woman
is from man’: the wording (he gune ek tou andros) is almost identical to
v. 8 (gune ex andros), where the point was to assert an imbalance
between man (the glory of God) and woman (the glory of man) — an imbalance in
the first creation that the veil is to screen out in the new creation. Having
moved forward from the old creation to the situation ‘in the Lord’ (vv. 7—10),
Paul is now in a position to look back at the old creation from the new
perspective and to see the togetherness of man and woman in the Lord already
foreshadowed there. The new creation redresses an imbalance in the old; but,
seen retrospectively, the old creation is also prophetic of the new.
Anticipations of the togetherness of man and woman in the Lord may be found in
the simplest and most obvious phenomena of the ®rst creation. Woman is from
man: as we have already seen, this intimate original unity is represented by
the Genesis narrator as the basis of the erotic movement of man towards woman
which is the original foundation of their relationship. But, even in the first
creation, the relation of man and woman is not wholly determined by eros.
Woman is from man, but man is also through woman. Man is the origin of woman,
but it is no less true that woman is the origin of man. Christ himself is ‘born
of woman’ (Gal. 4.4). Eve claims: ‘Through God, I have created a man [ektesamen
anthropon dia tou theou]’ (Gen. 4.1). The relation of mother to son is no
less fundamental and original than the relation of man to his wife. As man
becomes one flesh with woman in sexual union, so woman is one flesh with man in
conception, pregnancy, birth and nurture. The symmetry is inscribed in woman’s
very body, as the Pauline ‘through’ indicates. In the light of this original
togetherness with woman, the notion of male autonomy and primacy appears as a
post- Oedipal myth, a denial of the maternal origin that attempts to redress
the perceived imbalance of man’s dependence on woman for his very being. In the
Genesis text, however, the imbalance is redressed not by the myth of an
autonomous masculinity but by an erotic drive that is not a helpless reversion
to infantile dependence on the mother but a genuine initiative towards a woman
who is not the mother: a man leaves his father and mother and is joined
to his wife, so that the movement from woman to woman is not circular but
linear. From woman's perspective, the movement of the man towards union with
her flesh is balanced by a corresponding movement of man out of and away from
her flesh. In neither case does the togetherness of man and woman take the form
of a stifling embrace in which their distinctiveness is dissolved. In their
togetherness, they are allowed their own space.[xxxiii]
From the standpoint
of the togetherness of man and woman in the Lord, these complex and emotionally
charged realities may be seen as imperfect but actual anticipations of the
divinehuman koinonia of agape. Incorporated into this broader context, the
eros of man and woman is no longer a parody of agape but a parable.
. . .
and all things are from God
(v. 12b). The dialectic of male and female, origin and initiative, identity and
union is a purely creaturely reality that is relativized by the acknowledgment
that all this and the world in which it occurs is ‘from God’ as its absolute
origin. That divine origin is the basis for the fact that the togetherness of
man and woman in the created order can serve as a parable of the koinonia of
agape: for the two realities, distinct though they are, have a common source.
In the relation of the human creature to the divine creator, gender is relativized
and transcended; and this too is a parable of the divinehuman agape of the new
creation in Christ. In Christ there is neither Jew nor Greek, male nor female,
slave or free, and this relativizing of difference is anticipated in the
relation of creature to creator that precedes and grounds it. Gender is a creaturely
reality; the divine±human relation is not itself gendered. There is no more a
feminine other that would constitute God as masculine than there is a masculine
other that would constitute God as feminine. The creature does not play a
feminine role in relation to a masculine initiative of the creator, for what
passes for masculine initiative in the creaturely sphere does not even attain
the level of a caricature of the divine creatio ex nihilo. There is an
absolute qualitative difference between the two realities.
The gendering of the
one who creates ex nihilo is the fabrication of an image, in de®ance of
the second commandment. A particularly clear example, expressive of a
platonizing homoeroticism and misogyny, may be seen on the ceiling of the Sistine
Chapel. In the most celebrated painting of this series, the hidden source of
the creator's masculinity is revealed in the erotic look that evokes the
answering look of the awakening Adam ± a look whose sacrament is the gesture in
which the divine lover's index ®nger reaches out to meet the rising ®nger of
the human beloved. The heavenly archetype of this homoerotic relationship is
represented by the creator's simultaneous embrace of the naked and youthful
Son, who looks upon the human beloved not as a rival but as a counterpart. In
the next panel, in stark contrast to the grace and lightness of the ®rst, Eve
stumbles awkwardly into being. The masculinity of the creator has already been
established by the homoerotic encounter with Adam, and the creation of woman
is the ®rst step downwards towards the Fall. Here the creator has lost his ease
and grace of movement. He stands motionless, his back bent. He is the Ancient
of Days, and he looks his age. His right hand appears to ward off the approach
of the emerging Eve, refusing her the gesture of love spontaneously imparted to
Adam. The gracelessness of the ®gures in this panel contrasts with the beauty
of the naked youths at its corners, who variously gaze at one another and
display themselves in an attempt to restore the all-male harmony that Eve’s
irruption has broken. This painting is in fact a concession to orthodoxy, for
in the next panel Eve’s true origins are revealed. This time it is her turn to
recline languidly on the ground, to gaze into the eyes of a divine other, and
to reach up to touch an outstretched hand — the hand of a female hgure with a
serpent’s body coiled around a tree. In her rapt devotion to her counterpart,
Eve is oblivious of Adam’s urgent warnings. (‘Adam was not deceived, but the
woman was deceived and became a transgressor’ (1 Tim. 2.14).) As in the Timaeus,
Man represents the Father from above, Woman the Mother from the chaos below.
Man and Woman enjoy same-sex relationships with the divinities they
acknowledge, and their apartness from one another is projected into the divine
realm.
If ‘all things are
from God’ and if gender is a purely creaturely reality, then the projection of
gender onto divinity is exposed as misogynistic and idolatrous.27
Judgefor
yourselves: is it properfor a woman to pray to God with uncovered head? (v. 13). Earlier,
it was the woman who ‘prays or prophesies’ who is to be veiled (v. 5); now, it
is the woman who ‘prays to God’. When prayer is associated with prophecy, it is
clear that the woman in question is articulating the word of God to the
congregation and the responsive word of the congregation to God. But when
prayer is mentioned without prophecy, her role as leader is less clear and her
veiling may now become the condition of her presence at Christian worship. Her
veiling will then correspond to her silence: within Christian worship, she will
be both invisible and inaudible. It is only in the single reference to prophecy
(v. 5) and in the identihcation of the veil as women’s exousia (v. 10)
that this passage explicitly resists assimilation to the later silencing of
women in church (14.34 — 5).
27 In the opinion of E. H. Gombrich, 'It
is hardly an exaggeration to say that the picture of God the Father — as it has
lived in the minds of generation after generation, not only of artists but of
humble people, who perhaps have never heard the name of Michelangelo — was
shaped and moulded through the direct and indirect influence of these great
visions in which Michelangelo illustrated the act of creation’ (The Story of
Art, London: Phaidon Press, 16th edn 1995, 312). If there is any truth in
this, then the theological need for a critique of these paintings is obvious.
William Blake shows more perception than most in his 'Elohim creating Adam’ (c.
1795), a savage caricature of Michelangelo’s painting.
By the
time of 1 Clement, the silence of women has become — at least for the author —
the traditional norm to which the church at Corinth is recalled out of ‘the
abominable and unholy uprising [stasis], alien and foreign to the elect of God,
which a few rash and self-willed persons have kindled . . . ’ (1 Clem. 1.1).
Before the trouble started, the young were taught subservience to their rulers
and women were instructed to remain ‘in the rule of submission’ (en to kanoni
tes hupotages) to their husbands (1.3). But then, ‘the dishonourable rose
up against the honourable, the unknown against the renowned, the foolish
against the wise, the young against the elders [tous presbuterous]
(3.3). The cause of the uprising was ‘jealousy’ (zelos), which ‘has
estranged wives from husbands and made of no effect the saying of our father
Adam, “This is now bone of my bone and flesh of my flesh’’’ (6.3). The young
and the women are again set over against the elders as the author appeals for a
return to the church’s traditional order. ‘Let us respect those who rule us,
let us honour the elders [tous presbuterous], let us instruct the young
in the fear of God, let us lead our women to what is good . . . Let them make
the gentleness of their tongue manifest by their silence [to epieikes tes
glosses auton dia tes siges phaneron poiesatosan], let them not give their
affection in a partisan spirit [kata proskliseis], but in holiness to
all alike who fear God’ (21.6—7).
The
silencing of women means that the link between the veil and the authority to
speak is broken, so that the veil becomes the uniform condition of woman in
church. According to Tertullian, the Corinthian church understands the
apostle’s imposition of the veil to apply to all women alike (De virginibus
velandis, 8); indeed, this is the custom of the majority of churches
throughout Greece, although some impose the veil only on married women (2).
Tertullian commends the Corinthian practice to the churches of the west, where
the less stringent practice is the norm. The veil that the apostle imposes on
‘every woman’ (including ‘virgins’) seems consistent with the fact that ‘it is
not permitted to a woman to speak in the church, or to teach, to baptize, to
offer, or to lay claim to a male function such as the priestly office’ (9).
Despite this, the veil is for Tertullian the symbol of woman’s power, and not
of her weakness or subordination.[xxxiv]
In his treatise On
the Veiling of Virgins, Tertullian both extends the discipline of the veil
to unmarried women and insists that married women should conceal their heads
fully, and not just partially. At both points, he is conscious of flying in the
face of local custom, but — under the influence of Montanism — he claims that
the new practices have been revealed by the Paraclete through prophetic
utterances. A Christian woman has reported a visionary experience in which she
was chastised by an angel for appearing in church with an uncovered neck. ‘To
us, the Lord has measured the extent of the veil by way of revelations. For a
certain sister of ours was thus addressed in visions by an angel, beating her
neck as if in applause: “Elegant neck, and deservedly bare! You should uncover
yourselves from the head down to the loins, so as to take full advantage of the
freedom of your neck!’’’ (De virg. vel., 17). This supernatural sarcasm
is taken as a sign that total concealment of the head and neck is required of
all women in church. If women are ‘scandalized’ by the stringent addition of
invisibility to their existing inaudibility, they should ‘learn to acknowledge
their own evil’ (3) — for it is only their own lust that makes them want to be
seen. ‘The same kind of eyes reciprocally crave after each other. Seeing and
being seen belong to the self-same lust [eiusdem libidinis est videri et
videre] (2). A woman ‘must necessarily be imperilled by exposing herself in
public, as she is penetrated by the gaze of untrustworthy and multitudinous
eyes, as she is is caressed [titillatur] by pointing fingers, as she is
too well loved, as she feels a warmth creep over her amid ardent embraces and
kisses. So the forehead hardens; so the sense of shame [pudor] wears
away’ (14). On the other hand, ‘Who will have the audacity to intrude with his
eyes upon a covered face [faciem clausam], an unfeeling face, a face
with the appearance of a frown? Every evil thought will be destroyed by that
expression of severity’ (15). Women should realize that their face endangers
their Christian brothers, young or old: ‘All ages are imperilled in your
person’ (17). The story of the seduction of the sons of God by the daughters of
men is a terrible warning. ‘A face so fair as to cast stumbling-stones as far
as heaven itself must surely be shaded’ (7).
This is a theology
of women’s power — a power which can be used in the service of the flesh
or of the spirit. It is a power to which women themselves lay claim, for the
demand for full concealment of the head by all women was revealed by the
Paraclete through a woman prophet. In demanding women’s total withdrawal from
the male gaze, Tertullian seeks to enforce not his own opinion or even the
requirements of holy scripture but a divine commandment revealed through a
woman prophet who is his own contemporary. After the ages of the Law and the
Gospel, representing infancy and youth, the present age of the Paraclete
represents maturity: those who ‘demand that virgins be wholly covered’ do so
because they have heard the Paraclete ‘prophesying to the present time’ (1).
Women and men who absent themselves from the sexual games prevalent even in the
church are promised that they too will prophesy. ‘Through the holy prophetess
Prisca [= Priscilla] it is proclaimed that the holy minister must know how to
administer holiness of life [sanctimoniam]. For purification (she says)
produces harmony, and they see visions; and turning their face downward, they
also hear salutary voices, as clear as they are secret’ (De exh. cast.,
10.5). The downturned face speaks of woman’s silence and invisibility in
church, here representing not her weakness but her power ± the power to see
visions and to receive heavenly revelations. The sphere of woman’s silence is
penetrated and shaped by her prior speech, which in the name of the Paraclete
can override the authority of tradition itself. The precondition of this speech
is the sexual self-purification whose symbol is the veil which marks woman’s
definitive rejection of the conventional games of seeing and being seen. Yet it
would be wrong to understand the veil as a rejection of the flesh itself. In
another of the revelations of the Paraclete through Prisca, it is said of those
who deny the resurrection of the flesh that ‘they are fleshly, and yet they
hate the flesh’ (De res. earn., 11). Through the licentiousness of their
lives,
the enemies of the flesh are its greatest friends. But from another point of
view, it is those who impose sexual continence on the flesh who honour it most
highly as God’s workmanship. In both temporal and eternal matters, ‘the flesh,
which is accounted the minister and servant of the soul, turns out to be also
its associate and co-heir’ (7). Virginity and sexual restraint within marriage
are themselves ‘fragrant offerings to God paid out of the good services of the
flesh’ (8).
In
this remarkable appropriation of the Pauline symbol of the veil, it is women’s
power that makes it improper for them to worship with uncovered head. The rule
of faith — that there is one God, the creator, whose son Jesus Christ was ‘born
of the Virgin Mary, crucified under Pontius Pilate, raised again the third day
from the dead, received in the heavens, seated now at the right hand of the
Father, destined to come to judge quick and dead through the resurrection also
of the flesh’ (De virg. vel., 1) — requires that the flesh that is eternally
honoured by God should also be honoured within the church by disciplines
revealed through the Paraclete to prophetically gifted _ 29
women.29
Does
not nature itself teachyou that it is dishonourable for a man to have long
hair, while for a woman long hair is her glory? For her hair is given to her as
a garment
(vv. 14—15). In itself, this might suggest that the issue at Corinth is not the
covering of the face with a veil but the covering of the head with the hair. If
long hair is already a ‘garment’ (peribolaion) provided by nature to
conceal the nakedness of the female head, what need is there to supplement
nature’s provision with the artifice of the veil? The issue would then be that
women at Corinth have had their hair cut short, like men; it would be in that
sense that their head is ‘uncovered’ (vv. 5, 6, 13). This interpretation makes
good sense of the movement of thought from verse 13 — ‘Is it fitting for a
woman to
29 A notorious passage at the beginning
of his De cultu feminarum has created the mistaken impression of
Tertullian as an arch-misogynist. This widespread view is effectively
criticized in F. Forrester Church, 'Sex and Salvation in Tertullian’, HTR 68
(1975), 83—101. The recognition of Montanism’s significance for feminist
theology (see Susanna Elm, 'Montanist Oracles’, in E. Schussler Fiorenza (ed.),
Searching the Scriptures, 11.131—8) should encourage reassessment of
Tertullian. pray
to God uncovered?’ - to verses 14-15, where the covering of the head is the
long hair that is nature’s gift.[xxxv] Yet
the earlier use of concealment language would be surprising if the issue is
simply hair-length; and in verse 6 Paul asserts that the woman who refuses to
be covered should have her hair cut short or shaved off altogether — in
which case her hair is not at present cut short, so that this cannot be
the point at issue. Verses 14—15 also offer no support for the view that Paul
is trying here to persuade the Corinthian women to bind up their unbound hair,
thereby ‘covering’ their heads. On that view, the idea that long hair is
woman’s glory and that as such it is a garment provided by nature would be
indistinguishable from the Corinthians’ own position. As in verses 5—6, the
point is that women’s long hair (as opposed to men’s short hair) is analogous
to the additional covering represented by the veil. In seeking to impose this
extra covering on women but not on men, Paul is following the example of nature
itself, which has similarly seen (it to provide women with an extra covering.
The limitations of
this argument are already noted by Calvin, who writes: ‘Paul here sets nature
before them as the teacher of what is proper. Now, he means by “natural” what
was accepted by common consent and usage at that time, certainly as far as the
Greeks were concerned. For long hair was not always regarded as a disgraceful
thing in men. Thus the poets are in the habit of speaking about the ancients
and applying to them the epithet “unshorn”. In Rome they did not begin to use
barbers until a late period, about the time of Africanus the Elder. When Paul
was writing these words, the practice of cutting hair had not yet been adopted
in Gaul or Germany. Yes, and more than that, indeed, it would have been a
disgraceful thing for men, just as much as women, to have their hair shaved or
cut. But since the Greeks did not consider it very manly to have long hair,
branding those who had it as effeminate, Paul considers that their custom,
accepted in his own day, was in conformity with nature’ (1 Corinthians,
235).[xxxvi]
But
if anyone wishes to be argumentative, we have no other custom, nor do the
churches of God
(v. 16). Many readers of Paul’s text have indeed wanted to argue with it and
with him, and have found in this hnal verse the collapse of a weak and
incoherent argument into a bare appeal to authority. Paul, writes John P.
Meier, ‘seems to have a sinking feeling that none of these arguments from
Scripture, reason and nature is going to carry the day against his opponents,
people who are contentious, obstinate, dogmatic, more interested in having a
hght and winning it than in the truth (philoneikos). Well, if anyone
wants to be contentious -, at this point, Paul does not even complete his
sentence. He breaks off all reasoned argument and delivers his ®at on
the basis of universal tradition ... As some commentators have noted, it is
ironical that in the charismatic Paul, the great Apostle of freedom, we have
the beginnings not only of natural law and natural theology in the Christian
Church, but also of apodictic canon law. One does wonder, in the light of verse
16, why verses 3-15 even exist. The appeal to universal church practice as the
dehnitive arbiter of a question does make theological reasoning look like so
much window dressing’ (‘On the Veiling of Hermeneutics’, 223).[xxxvii] Meier’s purpose is to compare the doubtful
argumentation of the Pauline text with the equally doubtful argumentation of
the Declaration on the Question of the Admission of Women to the Ministerial
Priesthood (or Inter Insigniores), published by the Congregation for
the Doctrine of the Faith in 1977. In both cases, an unthinking appeal to what
is supposed to be unchanging tradition partially conceals itself behind the
‘window dressing’ of pseudo-theological argument. At the root of the problem is
the fact that ‘the Declaration does not take historical-critical exegesis
seriously’ (226). That is, it does not make sufficient allowance for the
historical conditioning of the deliverances of tradition on the question of
women’s ministry, from the Pauline texts onwards. If we read the assertions of
Paul, Augustine or Aquinas within the context of their own philosophical
presuppositions and pragmatic strategies, we must recognize that they can no
longer be regarded as normative.
To ‘take
historical-critical exegesis seriously’ is evidently to read the biblical texts
as a whole — and not just this Pauline passage — in the light of the antithesis
between that which is ‘historically conditioned’ and that which is ‘normative’.
At point after point, what purports to be ‘normative’ will turn out to be
‘historically conditioned’. Thus, one legalistic hermeneutic gives rise to
another, as the old law of the text is overthrown by a new law derived from the
insights and prejudices of the present — a law which judges the text, ®nds it wanting,
and discards it.
In
opposition to the hermeneutics of historicism, it is more productive of
theological insight to refuse the role of the adversary and to allow the text
to unfold itself in its own way, attending carefully and patiently to an underlying
logic that is not always manifest, and criticizing misleading statements only
in order to attain a better understanding of the real subject matter of this
passage: the togetherness of man and woman in the Lord, within the koinonia of
agape.
This Page Intentionally Left
Blank
PART II
Concupiscentia: Romans 7
The veil
signifies the exclusion of eros from the inner life of the Christian community,
in which man and woman belong together in agape. Does this mean that it also
signifies the ‘negative attitude towards sexuality and the body’ for which
Christian faith is so often held to be responsible? This thesis presupposes a
contrast between an earlier era of sexual repression (variously associated
with ‘Victorian hypocrisy’ or with Paul and Augustine) and the present era of
sexual enlightenment. Freud is conventionally seen as the turning-point from
one era to the other, since it was he who ®rst gave voice to sex, enabling sex
to speak for itself and without shame. Paul and Augustine on the one hand, Freud
on the other, mark the opposite poles of contemporary telling and retelling of
the story of our sexual enlightenment.
Augustine’s view of
sexuality is based on the Pauline analysis of desire (epithumia,
concupiscentia) and of the ego caught within the opposition between ‘the
law of God’ and ‘the law of sin that is in my members’ (Rom. 7). In his later
theory of the ego as exposed to the contradictory demands of super-ego and id,
Freud shows himself to belong to the Pauline-Augustinian tradition. Far from
underwriting the modern assumption that we (unlike our predecessors) have now
discovered sexuality to be unproblematic, Freud recovers the
Pauline-Augustinian sense of the intractability of this sphere of human
experience. Paul’s epithumia, Augustine’s concupiscentia and
Freud’s libido all refer to the same impersonal, quasi-divine power to
which human existence is subjected. The purpose of a reading of Freud along
these lines is to make it possible to re-read the Pauline text (and its
Augustinian interpretation) as a critique of the contemporary discourse
of sex, which overlooks or represses the phenomena that contradict its claim
that, for us, sexuality is essentially unproblematic (chapter 3).
The
Pauline-Augustinian critique is no more than a negative corollary of a
trinitarian theology of divine grace which represents the fundamental
ethos of the Christian community (chapter 4). Here, there is a service of God
in the newness of the Spirit and not in the oldness of the letter ± the letter
of a law which, as the narratives of Israel's experiences in the wilderness
testify, both embodies God's claim on human life and is implicated in the
genesis of human resistance to this claim. The law of the Spirit of life gives freedom
from the law of sin, and ful®ls the promise of life which is the true goal of
the law of God. Christian sexual ethics is therefore not to be seen as a set of
perhaps rather archaic restrictions on sexual life, which need to be
accommodated to the insights and conventions of our own time if they are to
have any continuing ‘relevance'. The ‘restrictions' are simply a consequence
of the gift of freedom to participate, together with others, in the eternal
intradivine life opened up to us in the death and resurrection of Jesus and
through his Spirit. As such, they belong to the gospel. They are good news, not
bad; compassionate and merciful, not harsh or judgmental. They limit eros or
concupiscence only in the name of agape.
‘Do not
be conformed to this world but be transformed by the renewal of your mind, that
you may prove what is the will of God, what is good and acceptable and
perfect': the Pauline injunction applies also to the sphere of sexual life.
This nonconformity to the world and renewal of the mind gives a certain
critical detachment from the destructive myths underlying the contemporary
discourse of sex.
CHAPTER
THREE
It is a
familiar story, and it goes like this:
Sex is
natural. Sex is good. Sex is enjoyable. There is no need to be ashamed of it.
Indeed, we inflict serious psychological damage on ourselves if we attempt to
repress our sexuality. Repression stems from a negative view of the body, for
which Christianity is largely responsible. But to be embodied is to be innocent
not guilty, and the sexual conjunction of bodies celebrates this innocence in
the play of paradise. It is these truths about the human condition that our own
age has rediscovered; Eros, demonized for so long, is again found to be a god
who bestows on his devotees the bliss of participation in his own divinity. We
are now at last at home with our bodies, we are no longer ashamed of them. And
we are no longer ashamed to speak of that which so intimately concerns
our bodies. Sexual liberation is also (or even primarily) the liberation of speech.
What was formerly unsayable can now be spoken freely, without fear or
shame.
Or so it is said.
The story of our sexual liberation is told and retold in many different
versions; it is constantly updated, so as to incorporate new emphases
overlooked by earlier renderings; and various qualifications and nuances may be
added or subtracted. But in all these variations it is recognizably the same
story that is told and retold, so compelling that it imposes itself as
self-evidently true.
The story is
inscribed in language itself. ‘Sex’ — as a synonym for ‘sexual intercourse’, as
in the phrase ‘to have sex with’ — appears to be a coinage only of the past
fifty or sixty years. Originally used simply in the sense of ‘gender’, this
word acquired increasingly ‘sexual’ connotations from around the 1890s onwards
— as exemplihed in formulations such as ‘sex- act’, ‘sex-life’, ‘sex-drive’,
‘sex-organs’, ‘sex-appeal’, popular in the early decades of the twentieth
century. These formulations prepared for the moment when it became possible to
use ‘sex’ in a (relatively) independent secondary sense, as referring not to
gender but to the act of sexual intercourse itself. Unlike ‘sexual intercourse’
or ‘sex-act’, ‘sex’ is no longer a circumlocution. In itself, ‘intercourse’
refers to the dialogical movement of contact and communication between persons;
and ‘sexual’ identihes the ‘intercourse’ in question as that which is
characteristic of persons as male and female, as differentiated from one
another and related to one another by the polarity of sex. The vagueness
of‘intercourse’ is given the necessary precision by the adjective — so
effectively that ‘intercourse’ itself is often now equivalent to ‘sexual
intercourse’, and can be used in a non-sexual sense only with difhculty. Originally
as vague as the equivalent terms in phrases such as ‘sexual relations’, ‘sexual
connection’, ‘sexual conjunction’, ‘sexual union’ and ‘sexual act’,
‘intercourse’ has succumbed, as it were, to the gravitational pull of ‘sex’ and
its semantic range has been restricted. (‘Copulation’, ‘coition’ and ‘make
love’ have suffered the same fate.) Yet ‘sexual intercourse’ retains its
circumlocutory feel; the original vagueness of ‘intercourse’ continues to lend
it a certain neutrality and non-asser- tiveness. ‘Sex’, on the other hand, is
more assertive. And what it asserts is the right of the act in question to have
its own proper name, to announce itself in all its nakedness, without veiling
itself in circumlocution and without shame. To assert that ‘sex’ is natural,
good, enjoyable and not shameful is simply to articulate the ideology inherent
in the word itself. And yet the word strives to conceal its ideological content
and its assertiveness by laying claim to something of the neutrality of
‘sexual intercourse’. ‘Sex’ just is what the act in question is called;
it is what the participants in the act ‘have’ with each other. ‘Sex’ has
no intention of transgressing the limits of linguistic decorum. Aspiring to
neutrality, it denies its own assertiveness; wishing to be a natural feature of
language, it conceals its own very recent origin. Thus an English speaker may
express surprise to discover that a particular foreign language has no word
for 'sex' ± although English itself has only recently acquired its word for
'sex'.[xxxviii]
Sex is natural, sex
is good, sex is enjoyable; it speaks freely, without shame. Yet 'sex' has so
far been unable to establish itself securely as the proper, unproblematic,
non-circumlocutory name for the act in question. Had it succeeded in this,
'sexual intercourse' would now be redundant. The persistent use of this
expression ± although in a limited range of mainly literary contexts ±
registers a continuing preference for the circumlocutory veil rather than
direct naming. Circumlocution arises out of an enduring sense of the shame of
semantic nakedness ± in spite of the claim of 'sex' that the nakedness of
direct utterance is proper to the natural, good and enjoyable act that speaks
in it. 'Sex' and 'sexual intercourse' divide over the question of shame.
'Sex' is supported
by a profusion of 'popular', less formal expressions which variously assert or
assume the innocence, the enjoyableness, the excitement, the physicality or the
comic incongruity of the sexual act. For example, there is no trace of shame in
expressions such as 'sleep with/together' or 'go to bed with/together'. These
expressions evoke the excitement of an initial moment of 'breakthrough' into a
sexual relationship ± the excitement not only of the sexual partners but also
of third parties for whom the fact that A has 'gone to bed with' B
or that they 'sleep together' may be an important and absorbing topic of
conversation. To 'sleep together' or 'go to bed together' is the act of free
agents considered in abstraction from any prior commitments. This language does
not normally refer to the repeated, more or less regular sexual acts that occur
within marriage. Although husbands and wives go to bed together and sleep
together, husbands are not said to ‘go to bed with’ their wives and wives are
not said to ‘sleep with’ their husbands. ‘Sleeping together’ and ‘going to bed
together’ derive their frisson of excitement from their primary
association with extramarital rather than marital ‘sex’. One sleeps with or
goes to bed with a new sexual partner, and it is the newness of the
ensuing situation that is newsworthy and that creates the need for a
specialized vocabulary. In this vocabulary, the free, transgressive excitement
of the ‘extra-marital’ is tacitly contrasted with what are taken to be the
unexciting, repetitive routines of the ‘marital’.
‘Sex’,
aspiring to neutrality and comprehensiveness, relativizes the distinction
between the marital and the extra-marital by asserting that it is the same act
that is perfor med on both sides of the boundary. Married couples and unmarried
‘lovers’ all ‘have sex’; what they ‘have’ is the same, irrespective of the
legal status of their relationship. ‘Sex’ rejects — that is, it makes archaic —
the earlier distinction between ‘conjugal union’ (or ‘marital relations’) and
‘fornication’ — a term now regarded as tactless to the point of offensiveness.
‘Sex’ has nothing in common with those acts in which wanton men satisfy ‘their
carnal lusts and appetites, like brute beasts without understanding’ — to cite
the gloss on the term ‘fornication’ offered by the Book of Common Prayer.2 Those
who ‘have sex’ do not want to be compared to brute beasts without
understanding. ‘Sex’ may be natural, but it has nothing to do with the
copulation of animals; animals do not have sex any more than they go to bed
together. Those who have sex are free agents, freely exercising their right to
do what they wish with their own bodies.3 It
is true
2 The reference to 'men’s carnal lusts
and appetites’ occurs in an exhortation not to undertake marriage
itself'unadvisedly, lightly, or wantonly’. Marriage was 'ordained for a remedy
against sin, and to avoid fornication’, and to undertake it wantonly would be
to convert marriage itself into fornication. In the 1928 revision, the carnal lusts
and brute beasts have been eliminated; and 'ordained for a remedy against sin,
and to avoid fornication’ is replaced by 'ordained in order that the natural
instincts and affections, implanted by God, should be hallowed and directed
aright’ — a sign of modern fastidiousness and reticence about sexual matters.
3 As Linda Woodhead writes: 'When and
where sex takes place between consenting that sex may on occasion be
unfree: it may be said of a rape victim, for instance, that she was 'forced to
have sex', whereas it would not be said that she was 'forced to make love'. As
the proper, primary and comprehensive term for the sexual act, 'sex' must cover
unfree as well as free sexual acts. But its bias is towards a construal of the
act as the free choice of unconstrained partners. It is suspicious of what it
sees as the unwarranted intrusion of negative moral judgments into its amoral
paradise or playground. To have sex is to make love; love is good, and it is
good to make what is good; it is therefore good to have sex. The logic is
unanswerable because it has already been written into the terminology itself.
The
hegemony of 'sex' over this semantic field is challenged on the one side by the
circumlocution 'sexual intercourse', which ought to have become redundant but
has not, and on the other side by the overpoweringly negative connotations of
the term 'fuck', which may function as verb, noun or expletive, or in the
quasi-adjectival 'fucking'. Like the analogous 'shit', 'fuck' as an expletive
draws attention to the speaker's intense annoyance and frustration by a wilful
violation of linguistic decorum. The force of 'shit' as an expletive seems to
derive from disgust at what it names, human excrement — although the expletive
is not in itself an expression of disgust. The still more negatively charged
'fuck' may be explained along similar lines — in which case it preserves a
reaction of intense disgust at the sexual act, from which it derives its
transgressive force. The fact that 'fuck' is more negatively charged than
'shit' would then imply that the sexual act evokes a still more intense disgust
than does excrement. 'Fuck' appears to imply that 'sex' is or can be
disgusting and shameful. Yet, as we have seen, 'sex' is not disgusting or
shameful, it is natural, good and enjoyable. A book entitled The Joy of Sex
occasions no surprise, but a book entitled The Shame of Sex is
inconceivable. In principle, then, 'sex' should either have
adults liberalism views it as
sacrosanct per se. The freedom from which sexual activity arises is
understood as the undisputed ground of its justification and sanctification.
This holds good whatever forms such sexual activity may take, and whatever its
social consequences' ('Sex in a Wider Context', inJ. Davies and G. Loughlin
(eds.), Sex These Days: Essays on Theology, Sexuality and Society,
Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1997, 98 — 120; 100). made
‘fuck’ redundant (as it should have made ‘sexual intercourse’ redundant), or
it should have worked for its rehabilitation as a word that actually denotes
something that is natural, good and enjoyable. Despite the advocacy of D. H.
Lawrence, however, this word remains as transgressive as ever. Although
familiar to all adult native English speakers, it is rarely if ever used by a
signihcant proportion of them. Even hearing it uttered can be experienced as a
gross violation, an insult to one’s integrity. It is a word that is shunned and
feared. Why? Because it evokes the knowledge - which ‘sex’ represses - that
disgust and shame remain all too comprehensible as reactions to sexual acts in
which we too may be implicated. This word exposes the limits and limitations of
the sanitized world in which one ‘makes love’ or ‘has sex’.
Although it takes
pride in its own frankness and forthrightness, ‘sex’ is in fact deeply
disingenuous. Wishing to know and to promote only the joy of sex, it represses
the knowledge of the shame of sex. It denies the profound ambivalences
registered, in their different ways, by circumlocution and expletive. It
simpli- ®es complexities. Its determination to maintain its own innocence
makes it blind to the reality of guilt. Although it asserts its own neutrality,
it aligns itself all too readily with the sentimentality of ‘making love’ and
the casual frivolity of ‘sleeping together’. Conversely, it is uneasy about the
older framework within which ‘conjugal union’ or ‘marital relations’ used to
take place — a framework in which a ‘husband’ and ‘wife’ are joined together in
‘marriage’, one of the purposes of which is to establish a ‘family’. Under the
impact of sex, these words — husband, wife, marriage, family — have acquired a
‘conservative’, slightly archaic ring, although the social arrangement they
represent is still very common. The words are still in use, but they now generate
a certain unease. Sex is not interested in marriage. All sex is
‘extra-marital’, in the sense that ‘marital status’ is irrelevant to it. If sex
occurs within marriage, it does so irrespective of marriage; one does not speak
of ‘marital sex’. Sex favours a different language: that of ‘relationships’,
which may be ‘long term’ or ‘stable’ but which are at every moment sustained
purely by the free choice of the two ‘partners’. Integral to this sex is the
concept of ‘contraception’, which ensures the integrity of sex as a
self-contained held by protecting the partners from the unwanted epiphenomena
of conception, pregnancy, birth and parenthood. Sex is natural, but sex needs
technology to protect it from nature. Without the technology of contraception, sex
is not sex.
These linguistic
phenomena indicate that the hegemony that ‘sex’ has established since its entry
into language is neither complete nor unproblematic. Although the
characteristic modern usage of this term has achieved spectacular success, anomalies
remain. The survival of circumlocution and expletive indicate that the shame
and disgust they express remain comprehensible even within the new regime. The
attempt to archaize and problematize ‘husband’, ‘wife’, ‘marriage’, ‘family’
flies in the face of a social reality in which traditional, premodern
assumptions about ‘adultery’ or ‘unfaithfulness’ often survive intact, along
with the terms themselves. Even in the more neutral ‘having an affair’, the
relevance of marriage is acknowledged in the fact that this phrase is used only
where at least one sexual partner is married to someone else. (The north
American ‘cheating on’ makes this point still more clearly.) Although ‘sex’
does accurately represent certain kinds of social reality, there is also a
curious and significant disjunction between the discourse of sex (the way ‘sex’
is theorized) and a complex social reality in which sexuality is associated not
only with love, joy and pleasure but also with shame and reticence, betrayal
and deceit, jealousy and anger, egotism and malice. ‘Sex’ turns a blind eye to
all this. It represses it.
Sex is natural, good
and enjoyable; it should speak itself freely and without shame. Although these
assertions are inherent in the word itself, the tautologies have a purpose.
They are directed against the repressive regime that is believed to have held
sway until the dawning of modern sexual enlightenment. ‘Sex’ is a monument to
this enlightenment and to its victory over the pre-modern darkness of
‘Victorian hypocrisy’ and of ‘Christianity’s negative attitude towards the
body’.4
4 The fact that the story of modern
sexual enlightenment is precisely a story (and in some respects a very odd and
implausible story) was demonstrated by Michel Ideologies need heroes and
villains, and the ideology of ‘sex’ has no difficulty in identifying suitable
figures. If we ask who was responsible for ‘Christianity’s negative attitude
towards the body’, the answer is obvious: it was St Paul and St Augustine,
those masters of repression. If we ask who was responsible for bringing the
reign of ‘Victorian hypocrisy’ to an end, the answer is equally obvious: it was
Sigmund Freud. Freud restored to light what Paul, Augustine and the Victorians
concealed in darkness.
According to Paul,
periods of sexual abstinence in marriage should be short-lived, ‘lest Satan
tempt you through lack of selfcontrol’. The young do not sin if they marry,
‘for it is better to marry than to be aflame with passion’. In such statements
as this, as Peter Brown notes, ‘The dangers of porneia, of potential
immorality brought about by sexual frustration, were allowed to hold the center
of the stage. By this essentially negative, even alarmist strategy, Paul left a
fatal legacy to future ages . . . In the future, a sense of the presence of
“Satan”, in the form of a constant and ill-de®ned risk of lust, lay like a
heavy shadow in the corner of every Christian church’ (The Body and Society:
Men, Women and Sexual Renunciation in Early Christianity, 55).5 The
depiction of the conflict of mind and flesh in Romans 7 establishes, in a mere
hundred words or so, ‘the future course of Christian thought on the human
person . . . A weak thing in itself, the body was presented as lying in the
shadow of a mighty force, the power of the flesh . . . “The flesh’’ was
not simply the body, an inferior other to the self, whose undisciplined
stirrings might even at times receive a certain indulgent tolerance, as
representing the natural claims of a physical being. In all later Christian
writing, the notion of “the flesh’’ suffused the body with disturbing
associations’ (48). In Augustine, the Pauline ‘law of sin which dwells in my
members’ is traced back to the moment of the Fall when the bodies of Adam and
Eve ‘were
Foucault, in his History of
Sexuality, vol. i: An Introduction [1976], ET London: Allen Lane,
1979.
5 New York: Columbia University Press,
1988. Although Foucault’s significance is acknowledged (xvii—xviii), the
'repressive hypothesis’ that he identified and criticized remains basically intact
in Brown’s work. touched
with a disturbing new sense of the alien, in the form of sexual sensations that
escaped their control ... A tiny but ominous symptom ± in Adam's case, the
stirring of an erection over which he had no control ± warned them both of the
®nal slipping of the body as a whole from the soul's familiar embrace at death’
(416—17). ‘In Augustine’s piercing vision, the Roman city and the walls of the
married household within it — those solid, magnihcently self-reliant creations
of an ancient Mediterranean way of life — were now washed by a dark current of
sexual shame. Adam’s shame knew no frontiers’ (426—7). Augustine’s ‘distrust
of sexual pleasure’ was ‘a heavy legacy to bequeath to later ages’ (426).
It is this ‘legacy’
— so ‘heavy’ as to be ‘fatal’ — that our own century has at last dehnitively
rejected in its rediscovery of‘the natural claims of a physical being’. For us,
‘sexuality has come to wear a more comfortable face’ (xvii). Comfortable with
our bodies and our sexualities, we hnd it hard to understand how anything as
innocent, natural and pleasurable as the symptoms of sexual arousal could ever
have been found to be ‘disturbing’. At home again with the ‘indulgent
tolerance’ we think we see in pagan antiquity, we hnd Christian antiquity
deeply enigmatic. And yet this enigma plays an indispensable role in the story
of our sexual liberation: for narratives of enlightenment require a prior state
of darkness if our own breakthrough into light is to be commemorated with due
solemnity. The discovery of a ‘sex’ that is natural, good and enjoyable must be
narrated precisely as a discovery, an uncovering of what had previously
been concealed. Christianity’s ‘negative view of the body’ may be enigmatic,
but without it there would be no story of how we have learned to take a
‘positive view of the body’. ‘The body’ must be initially dehned in terms of
‘sexual renunciation’ (as in Brown’s subtitle) so that we in turn may redehne
it in terms of sexual fulhlment.
Narratives of
enlightenment deny ambivalence and complexity by assigning negativity to a
now-superseded past and positivity to a victorious present. They separate the
light from the darkness; they are comedies, not tragedies. In comedy, a history
of confusion and conhict resolves itself into the transparency of a happy
ending. In tragedy, confusion and conflict prove intractable, and resolution
can occur only within the severest constraints. Yet the Pauline and Augustinian
narratives of the body cannot properly be classified as tragedies - for both
Paul and Augustine believe that ‘where sin increased, grace abounded all the
more’ (Rom. 5.20). The war of ‘the law of my mind’ with ‘the law of sin which
dwells in my members’ (7.23) would only be a tragic conflict if the cry,
‘Wretched man that I am! Who will deliver me from this body of death?’ (v. 24)
were the last word. But it is thanksgiving that has the last word: ‘Thanks be
to God through Jesus Christ our Lord!’ (v. 25). If grace and thanksgiving are
set aside, the tension between the mind and the flesh would indeed be the
tragic truth of human nature. The mind, desiring to subject itself to the
demands of the law of God in which it delights, finds itself unable to master
the contrary desires of the rebellious flesh. Without grace and thanksgiving,
this almost unendurable tension is perhaps integral to being human.
To put the point
another way: the ego, desiring to subject itself to the demands of the
super-ego, finds itself unable to master the desires that arise out of the id.
To be human is to be subject to this intractable conflict. The language is, of
course, Freud’s. The father of twentieth-century sexual enlightenment turns out
to be deeply rooted in the Pauline and Augustinian tradition — not at all what
the narrative of sexual enlightenment had led us to expect.[xxxix]
THE LUST OF THE FLESH
The
Pauline text begins with a contrast between a past, ‘when we were in the flesh’
and when ‘the passions of sins, aroused by the law, were working in our members
to bear fruit for death’, and a present in which we belong not to the law but
to Christ, who ‘has been raised from the dead in order that we may bear fruit
for God’ (Rom. 7.5, 4). Freed from the law, our service of God is now ‘in
newness of the Spirit and not in oldness of the letter’ (v. 6). The letter is
the law’s inscribed demand, ‘Thou shalt . . . ’ or ‘Thou shalt not . . . ’ In
this model of the divinehuman relationship, God is characterized as the one
who subjects humans to his command and humans are characterized as those who
are thereby subjected. The divine-human relationship is a master-slave
relationship. That does not make it unjust. ‘The commandment is holy and just
and good’ (v. 12) - its goodness is twice reiterated in subsequent verses (vv.
13, 16). The command of this divine master to this human slave is ‘just’
because it addresses the human being as a creature whose very being is derived
ex nihilo, without remainder, from the creative act of the divine being;
and it is ‘good’ because it is addressed to the human creature not to compel it
to sacrihce its own wellbeing for the well-being of its master, but to ensure
that in the service of its divine master it hnds its own true well-being. This
master-slave relationship, as promulgated by Moses and actualized within
Judaism, derives from God’s own holiness, justice and goodness, and in it the
human subject rightly hnds satisfaction and joy (vv. 16,22):
The
law of the Lord is perfect, reviving the soul. The testimony of the Lord is
sure, making wise the simple. The precepts of the Lord are right, rejoicing the
heart. The commandment of the Lord is pure, enlightening the eyes. The fear of
the Lord is clean, enduring for ever. The ordinances of the Lord are true, and
righteous altogether. More to be desired are they than gold, even much ®ne
gold; sweeter also than honey and drippings of the honeycomb. (Ps. 19.7-10)
Every
human master-slave relationship is a caricature and distortion of the
divine-human relationship as characterized by the Law of Moses. To hnd in
Judaism a heteronomy which unjustly denies the proper autonomy of the human
subject is a slander deriving from Gentile malice and ignorance of God.
Yet all this is
declared to be ‘old’, surpassed, superseded and transcended in the redehnition
of the divine-human relationship accomplished by Jesus (a Jew) and his Spirit,
and proclaimed by the apostle (also a Jew). If the Law is understood in
abstraction from Christ, as the dehnitive account of the divinehuman
relationship and not as preliminary and provisional, a radical flaw appears
which prevents the divine goodness from attaining its goal, which is true human
well-being. The flaw is not in the Law itself, or in God (‘By no means!’ (Rom.
7.7)). The flaw arises from a catastrophic event that has overtaken the human
partner in the divine-human relationship: the coming of the Law has manifested
and brought to the surface a previously latent resistance to God. The Law
forbids even the desire for the objects it prohibits, and the unforeseen result
is that the forbidden desire springs to life, overwhelming the self and
depriving it of the life and well-being in communion with God that the Law
intends (vv. 7-13). The human body, originally identical to the human ego and
at the same time its vehicle, becomes ‘flesh’ (vv. 5, 18, 25), the site of
uncontrolled ‘passions’ (v. 5) and ‘desire’ (vv. 7-8). The body as ‘flesh’ is
withdrawn from the control of the ego, and the ego, aligned with the Law of
God, looks on helplessly as it sees how ‘my members’ are obedient to ‘another
law’ (v. 23), whose authority I reject but which has nevertheless taken up
residence at the heart of my being and established its authority. The ego,
longing to enjoy the life and well-being intended by the Law, finds itself
trapped in a body that obeys a quite different logic. This analysis of the
human self as caught in the tension between the Law and the Flesh has evoked
echoes that continue to reverberate.
In Augustine’s
reading of this passage, the ‘desire’ (epithumia) that overwhelms the
ego and prevents the doing of the good is pre-eminently sexual desire (concupiscentia).[xl] ‘The law of sin
which is in my members’ (v. 23) is therefore not distributed among my members
in anarchic fashion, each member being impelled along its own path
independently of the others. The Law of Sin is far from anarchic. Having
removed the body as a whole from the control of the ego (or ‘mind’ (vv. 23,
25)), Sin subjects the bodily members to the primacy of a single member, which
it appoints as its surrogate and through whom it exercises its power. This is
clear from the Genesis narrative of the Fall. When Adam and Eve transgressed
the divine commandment, their ®rst act was to conceal their genitals in shame
at their nakedness. They did so because their assumption of control over their
own bodies, in the act of eating the forbidden fruit, had met its due
retribution in the loss of control over their own bodies that accompanied the
new perception of the nakedness of the other. In the presence of the other as
naked, involuntary physiological changes took place ± most obviously in the
case of Adam, in the erection of his penis, but no less actually in the case of
Eve, whose desire is already for her husband (Gen. 3.16), and is manifested in
corresponding symptoms such as the engorgement of the genital region and the
lubrication of the vagina. These physiological changes were not in themselves
new, for they were already entailed in the creation of humans as male and
female and in the divine command to be fruitful and multiply. Sexual intercourse
was corrupted by the devil, but it was not invented by the devil; the devil
lacks the divine creativity that is still evident even in the corrupted form of
the sexual act (the only form known to us). What was new was the fact that the
physiological changes were no longer subject to the control of the mind but now
seemed to obey an alien power. Until now, the bodily movements associated with
sexual intercourse had been as voluntary as the bodily movements associated
with eating. Like eating, sexual intercourse was pleasurable, but in both cases
the pleasure was commensurate with the natural, divinely ordained goal
underlying the grati®- cation of desire: the maintenance of life in the one
case, the reproduction of life in the other. The pleasures of food and sex were
therefore orderly pleasures, in the sense that they ®tted harmoniously within
the orderly rhythm of a life ordained by God and oriented towards God.
Through the eating
of the forbidden fruit, sexual pleasure falls out of that orderly pattern and
becomes disordered and disordering. In place of a previously orderly desire,
Adam and Eve are overwhelmed by a tidal wave of concupiscentia that they
can no longer control. In the presence of the other’s nakedness, the whole body
is reordered around the genitals and the longing for bodily union which is
visibly and palpably expressed in them. The body, which had been both identical
to the person and the vehicle of the person, is now charged with an intense and
impersonal energy which holds the body of the other within its held of
attraction, and threatens to deprive it of all power of movement other than the
movement of physical union. Concupiscentia is both the promise of
pleasure and the threat of unfreedom, and it is the body itself - the naked
body, which is also the natural body, created by God - that is the site of its
promise and threat. The body is no longer simply the person as such or the
vehicle of the person; it has become an intensely ambivalent object,
fascinating and enticing but also overpowering and disturbing. In the symptoms
of sexual arousal that (according to Augustine) follow the eating of the
forbidden fruit, Adam and Eve involuntarily acknowledge both their own body and
the body of the other as charged with an impersonal power that threatens their
freedom of movement - a power that demands discharge through sexual union and
orgasm. This power, previously one among a number of mutually limiting,
benehcent powers to which human life was subject, has now taken control of the
body as a whole: the natural body, received from the hand of God as the
physical manifestation of the person, has become the ‘naked’ body, the
genitally oriented body that incites sexual arousal. The threat that this
distorted body poses to oneself and to others can be warded off only by
concealing it. With rudimentary garments of hg-leaves, Adam and Eve conceal
their nakedness; that is, although leaving most of their flesh exposed and
naked, they conceal their genitals and thus the new reality of the genitally
oriented, libidinally charged body that has supervened upon the natural body
created by God. Humans clothe themselves as a defence against the power of
concupiscence. Forced underground by this act of repression, concupiscence may
at any time break through the surface, as if without warning, aroused perhaps
by the mere sight of flesh or even by the hints of the shape and texture of
flesh that clothing continues to per mit. If this seems a trivial and innocent
phenomenon, it is worth recalling that the purest expression of the reality of
concupiscence is found in the event of rape. Rape is what happens when
concupiscence is uninhibited by social constraints and ®nds itself capable of
direct expression.
For Augustine as for
Paul and for Freud, there is much more to be said about the human condition
than that it is subject to the disruptive power of concupiscentia, epithumia
or libido. Yet, for Augustine and Paul although differently for Freud,
it is at this point that symptoms of the intransigence of human resistance to
God are most clearly visible. Thus the present-tense section of Romans 7 (vv.
14±25) can be read as a vivid rendering of the ego's experience of itself as
caught in the tension between the law of God and the exorbitance of sexual
desire. For Augustine, this is the experience of the ego that has become
conscious of its true situation, the ego as enlightened by divine grace and reempowered
by divine grace at least to will the good, even if not to ful®l it. The speaker
wills what is good but does what is evil, not in the sense that there is no
true human love of God or of neighbour (which would be to deny the reality of
grace) but in the sense that love of God and of neighbour is never pure (except
in the case of Jesus) but is always mingled with the residue of concupiscence.
Freud too sees the
ego as caught in the tension between ‘law' and ‘flesh', or, in his own
terminology, between super-ego and id. As we shall see, the concept of the
‘super-ego', first clearly outlined in a relatively late text dating from 1923,
marks a shift from a Platonic model of the self to a Pauline and Augustinian
one.
MODELLING THE PSYCHE
Eager to
establish that psychoanalysis is a true ‘science', and thus a genuine
contribution to the project of ‘science' as a whole, Freud at one point
inscribes the resistance to the new science within the history of resistance to
science that looms so large within science's self-image. This resistance arises
from science's destruction of the illusions projected by ‘men's naive
self-love’. Human self-love suffered a first blow when Copernicus established
‘that our earth was not the centre of the universe but only a tiny fragment of
a cosmic system of scarcely imaginable vastness’. The second blow came when,
‘not without the most violent contemporary opposition’, Darwin, Wallace and
others ‘destroyed man’s supposedly privileged place in creation and proved his
descent from the animal kingdom and his ineradicable animal nature’. All that
is past history. But now, ‘human megalomania suffers its third and most
wounding blow', as psychoanalysis shows that the human ego ‘is not even master
in its own house, but must content itself with scanty information of what is
going on unconsciously in its mind . . . Hence arises the general revolt
against our science’ (1.326).8
This attempt to
write psychoanalysis into the story of the rise of science actually subverts
that story at a crucial point. The story of the rise of science is at the same
time the story of the fall of religion; science rises precisely as, point by
point, it brings about religion’s downfall. In its quest for an illusory
consolation through the projection of a divine father-surrogate, religion
belongs to the childhood of the human race; and ‘men cannot remain children for
ever' but must allow science to initiate them into adulthood by providing them
with an ‘education to reality’ (12.233). Psychoanalysis proves its scientific
credentials by furthering the scientific critique of religion. Yet its claim
that the ego ‘is not even master in its own house’ is actually analogous to the
religious critique of the comforting illusion of the autonomous, self-suf®cient
ego (an illusion that helps to generate the scienti®c ego and to make its
®ctions plausible). In pointing to the universality of repressed, prohibited
impulses, ‘psychoanalysis is simply confirming the habitual pronouncement of
the pious: we are all miserable sinners’ (13.129). The pious have never
believed that the ego is master in its own house. They have always known that
the ego is subject to impulses prohibited by the law of God which continue to
torment and seduce it, and that order can be restored only
8 Here and elsewhere in this chapter,
page references are to The Penguin Freud Library, ed.
Angela Richards and Albert
Dickson, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1973—85. when the ego abandons the
foolish project of becoming master in its own house and allows the house of the
body to become the temple of the Holy Spirit. In the psychoanalytical account
of redemption, it is psychoanalysis itself which ministers to the ego in its
distress and enables it to survive its own overthrow.[xli]
The ego is not even
master in its own house because it lacks the freedom to determine who shall
gain admittance to it. In the Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis (1915±17),
the house image is developed into a full-scale picture of the topography and
dynamics of the human mind. We are invited to
compare
the system of the unconscious to a large entrance hall, in which the mental
impulses jostle one another like separate individuals. Adjoining this entrance
hall there is a second, narrower, room ± a kind of drawing-room ± in which
consciousness, too, resides. But on the threshold between these two rooms a
watchman performs his function: he examines the different mental impulses, acts
as a censor, and will not admit them into the drawing-room if they displease
him . . . The impulses in the entrance hall of the unconscious are out of sight
of the conscious, which is in the other room; to begin with they must remain
unconscious. If they have already pushed their way forward to the threshold and
have been turned back by the watchman, then they are inadmissible to
consciousness; we speak of them as repressed. But even the impulses
which the watchman has allowed to cross the threshold are not on that account
necessarily conscious as well; they can only become so if they succeed in
catching the eye of consciousness. We are therefore justi®ed in calling this
second room the system of the preconscious. (1.336—7)
The ego
(or consciousness) at least appears to be master in its own drawing-room.
Guests enter and circulate, and the ego attends to them or disregards them, as
it chooses. The mind is full of latent, pre-conscious ideas and images that can
be summoned up when required, at a moment's notice. The ego cannot attend to
all its guests at once, but they remain its guests. Their faces are
familiar; they are the ®xed points around which mental life circulates, giving
it its own particular identity and texture. It is memory that ensures the
stability and security of the ego within the sphere of its dominion. Yet the
ego has overlooked something. Master of its own drawing-room, it has failed to
notice that its entrance hall is occupied by an unruly proletarian mob, and
that it is only the vigilance of the servant at the doorway that prevents the
masses from bursting into the drawing-room itself, inflicting insult and injury
on the ego and its guests. The guardian of the threshold distinguishes genuine
guests from the mob by various means. Those who are to gain admittance must be
appropriately attired for the drawingroom; those who are turned back are
improperly dressed, and some indeed are entirely naked — worse still, they
flaunt their nakedness and their sexuality with flagrant disregard for all the
rules of propriety. Those who gain admittance indicate that they are worthy to
enter by their speech and their deportment; those who are turned back reveal
their unworthiness in the vulgarity of their speech and gestures. Occasionally
a member of the mob will elude the vigilance of the ‘watchman’ or ‘censor’ and
take a few steps over the threshold before being ejected. On the whole, the
servant is remarkably successful at concealing from his master the gross
disorder that is occurring within his own walls. Yet the concealment is not
entirely successful. Even the most diligent servant cannot prevent one from
becoming aware, perhaps through the tiniest of symptoms, that all is not well.
The guests themselves will be marked by the trauma of their entrance.10
The ego,
the watchman and the unruly passions: this anthropological model is
reminiscent more of Plato than of Paul. In Plato’s Republic (414B), the
governing of the proletariat is assigned to two classes, the ‘rulers’ (archontes)
or ‘guardians’ (phulakes) and the ‘auxiliaries’ (epikouroi) or
‘assistants’ (boethoi); it is the role of the auxiliaries to put into
effect the decisions of the rulers. The just ordering of the life of the
individual follows this model of the just ordering of society. In the soul,
there is a
10 The 'censor’ image occurs already in The
Interpretation of Dreams (1900), where the dream-censor plays a crucial
role in distorting and concealing the true meaning of a dream. 'This censorship
acts exactly like the censorship of newspapers at the Russian frontier, which
allows foreign journals to fall into the hands of the readers whom it is its
business to protect only after a quantity of passages have been blacked out’
(4.676—7). rational
element (to logistikon) and an element that is irrational, concerned
only with the appetites and pleasures (439D); a third, intermediate element,
corresponding to the 'auxiliaries', may be seen in the 'spirit' or
'indignation' (thumos) which allies itself with the ruling logos
in its struggle to control the desires (epithumiai) or passions (440B).
This third element may be compared to a sheep-dog who controls the unruly sheep
in obedience to the will of the shepherd (440D). Without the auxiliaries, the
rulers would be powerless to control the much more numerous class of those who
devote themselves solely to pleasure and the passions. In Freud's version of
this model, the role of thumos is played by the watchman at the door,
whose forcible ejection of would-be intruders protects the ego or reason from
being overwhelmed. Yet Freud's watchman keeps the ego ignorant of the fact that
the entrance hall has been occupied by the mob. His task is not simply to suppress,
as in Plato, but to repress - to suppress so effectively and thoroughly
that the act of suppression is not even perceived as such. The Platonic logos
knows exactly who is its enemy and who is its ally; the Freudian ego remains
pathetically ignorant of its enemy, and is at a loss to explain the symptoms of
disorder that make themselves felt even in the orderly world of its own drawingroom
± despite the efforts of the watchman. In addition, the pleasures and passions
that oppose the control of the Platonic logos live elsewhere in the
city, not in the ruler's own home. Policing them is not a problem. In Freud,
they have left the slums and tenements on the other side of the city and have
taken up residence within the elegant mansions of the ruling classes. The
autocracy of the police state is threatened by proletarian revolution: at this
point Freud's lectures, published in 1917, correspond to the unfolding
political situation in Petrograd or Moscow. Psychoanalysis aligns itself with
the insurgents in their hostility to the guardian of the threshold. It seeks to
compel the uncomprehending ego to recognize what is going on under its own
roof, to acknowledge that it is not master even in its own house, and to
negotiate some new modus vivendi with the libidinous occupants of the
entrance hall. In psychoanalytic interpretation, the work of the over-zealous
watchman is undone: what is unconscious is transformed into what is conscious,
and the ego becomes ‘conciliatory towards the libido and inclined to grant it
some satisfaction’, its repugnance being diminished ‘by the possibility of
disposing of a portion of it by sublimation’ (1.508).
In The Ego and
the Id (1923), a new, more precise terminology is introduced. The realm
represented in the image by the entrance hall is now described as the ‘id’ (das
Es); and the anonymous watchman or censor who guards the boundary between the
realms of id and ego (das Ich) is now named the ‘super-ego’ (das Uber-Ich)
Once a servant, corresponding to the Platonic ‘auxiliaries’, he is now master
of the ego; no longer content with the role of repression or censorship, he has
taken upon himself the task of judging and criticizing the ego itself. The
super-ego is the internalized representative of authority hgures such as
parents and parent-substitutes, and its harsh commands and prohibitions (‘Thou
shalt . . . ’ and ‘Thou shalt not’) are an important element in the genesis of
religion. Thus the Platonic model of the self is replaced by a Pauline model in
which the ego is torn between the conflicting imperatives of the super-ego
(‘the Law of God’) and the id (the realm that is under the sway not of the ego
but of ‘the Law of Sin’). The promotion of the watchman or censor to
‘super-ego’ results in a transformation of the earlier model, and we must
trace the rationale for this transformation.
Fundamental to
psychoanalysis is the distinction between ‘conscious’ and ‘unconscious’, which
originates in the discovery that an important class of mental events,
perceptible only through their symptoms, is unconscious. Yet an identification
between the conscious realm and the ego and between the unconscious realm and
the repressed turns out to be misleading. As we have seen, the ego which
receives its guests in its drawing-room is not conscious of all of them at
once, but directs its consciousness from one to another in turn.
A
state of consciousness is characteristically very transitory; an idea that is
conscious now is no longer so a moment later, although it can become so under
certain conditions that are easily brought about. In the interval the idea was
— we do not know what. We can say that it was latent, and by this we
mean that it was capable of becoming conscious at any time. Or, if we
say that it was unconscious, we shall also be giving a correct
description of it. (11.352)
Unconsciousness
or pre-consciousness is therefore fundamental to the life of the ego itself.
Thus ‘we have two kinds of unconscious - the one that is latent but capable of
becoming conscious, and the one which is repressed and which is not, in itself
and without more ado, capable of becoming conscious’ (11-353)- This situation
may be represented by the symbols Cs. (conscious), Pcs.
(pre-conscious) and Ucs. (unconscious); since the Cs. derives its
ideas not only from the Pcs. but also from sense-perception, the symbol Pcpt.
is also required. But there is also a third kind of unconscious (in the broader
sense), which, like the Pcs., belongs to the ego, but which, like the Ucs.,
is subject to repression. When, during psychoanalysis, a patient’s free
associations fail, this is a sign both that he is approaching the realm of the
repressed and that he is experiencing a resistance to his proceeding any
further. We tell him that he is encountering a resistance,
but
he is quite unaware of the fact, and, even if he guesses from his unpleasurable
feelings that a resistance is now at work in him, he does not know what it is
or how to describe it. Since, however, there can be no question but that this
resistance emanates from his ego and belongs to it, we find ourselves in an
unforeseen situation. We have come across something in the ego itself which is
also unconscious, which behaves exactly like the repressed - that is, which
produces powerful effects without itself being conscious and which requires
special work before it can be made conscious. (11.355-6)
The ego
is, it seems, unaware of the activity of the guardian of the threshold,
although he is the servant of the ego who faithfully carries out the ego’s
unconscious will.
Since the
unconscious penetrates so deeply into the ego itself (in the form of the Pcs.
and the as-yet unnamed analogue to the Ucs.), a division of the psyche into
‘ego’ and ‘unconscious’ is misleading. Another term is needed to set in
opposition to ‘ego’, and this has been provided by the physician Georg
Groddeck, who is never tired of insisting that what we call our ego behaves
essentially passively in life, and that, as he expresses it, we are ‘lived’ by unknown and
uncontrollable forces ... I propose to take [this] into account by calling the
entity which starts out from the system Pcpt. and begins by being Pcs.
the ‘ego’, and by following Groddeck in calling the other part of the mind,
into which this entity extends and which behaves as though it were Ucs.,
the ‘id’ . . . We shall now look upon an individual as a psychical id, unknown
and unconscious, upon whose surface rests the ego, developed from its nucleus,
the Pcpt. system ... It is easy to see that the ego is that part of the
id which has been modified through the medium of the Pcpt.-Cs.; in a
sense it is an extension of the surface-differentiation. Moreover, the ego
seeks to bring the influence of the external world to bear upon the id and its
tendencies, and endeavours to substitute the reality for the pleasure principle
which reigns unrestrictedly in the id. For the ego, perception plays the part
which in the id falls to instinct. The ego represents what may be called reason
and common sense, in contrast to the id, which contains the passions . . . Thus
in its relation to the id [the ego] is like a man on horseback, who has to hold
in check the superior strength of the horse; with this difference, that the
rider tries to do so with his own strength while the ego uses borrowed forces.
(11.362)11
The
language and conceptuality here are still Platonic. The ego and the id
correspond to the reason and the passions, identified respectively with
‘reality’ (Plato’s ‘truth’) and ‘pleasure’; and the image of the rider and his
horse is descended from the myth of the charioteer in the Phaedrus. For
Plato, the ego or reason originates ‘from above’; it is a portion of the
immortal soulsubstance made by the demiurge himself. Its entanglement with
irrational desire is alien to its true nature, and derives from the demiurge’s
decision that in the human person immortal soul or reason should be combined
with the shifting elements of the maternal ‘receptacle of becoming’ (Timaeus
41A—47E). For Freud, the ego originates ‘from below’, out of the id. From the
encounter between the desires of the id and external reality as conveyed by
sense-perception, there arises, on and just beneath the surface of the id, that
modi®cation of the id that we know as the ego and that mediates between id and
reality. This origin
11 Freud acknowledges that Groddeck is
indebted to Nietzsche for the distinction between Ich and Es. In Beyond
Good and Evil, for example, Nietzsche criticizes the Cartesian cogito
on the grounds that 'a thought comes when “it’’ wants, not when “I” want; so
that it is a falsification of the fact to say: the subject “I’’ is the
condition of the predicate “think’’. It thinks . . .’ (§17; ET
Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1973)- within
the id means that, unlike the Platonic reason, the ego has no energy of its own
and is forced to draw its energy from the id, 'the great reservoir of libido'
(11.369^. Thus, for Freud in contrast to Plato, embodiment is proper to the
human psyche. The absence of the older dualistic metaphysic can be traced back
not just to the 'materialism' of modern science but to the Judaeo-Christian
doctrine of creation. Yet, paradoxically, the difficulties of the embodied
psyche are still greater for Freud than for Plato.
It is
the concept of the super-ego that transforms this broadly Platonic model of the
psyche into a Pauline one. The super-ego originates in the Oedipus complex, and
since in 1923 — the date of The Ego and the Id — Freud's account of the
distinctive female form of the Oedipal situation was still undeveloped, we
follow the more familiar account, oriented towards the male.[xlii] For the small child, the original sexual object is
the maternal breast, and the original relation to the mother therefore differs
from the original relation to the father, which is characterized not by sexual
attraction ('object-cathexis') but by 'identification'. The Oedipal situation
arises when the father is perceived as an obstacle to the grati®cation of the
child's sexual wishes in relation to the mother: 'His identification with his
father then takes on a hostile colouring and changes into a wish to get rid of
his father in order to take his place with his mother. Henceforth his relation
to his father is ambivalent . . .' (11.371). In 'normal' development, the small
boy will be compelled to abandon his desire for his mother and will identify
himself all the more intensely with the father, the source of the original
prohibition. This identi®cation will express itself positively in a desire to
be like the father, and negatively in submission to the paternal prohibition:
certain things are indeed the father's prerogative, and the child must renounce
all claim to them. In the emergence of the super-ego or ego ideal, the Oedipus
complex is overcome. The paternal decree, forbidding possession of the mother,
has now been accepted and internalized. (A later variant of this decree is the
paternal prohibition of infantile masturbation, a genital substitute for the
original oral sexual satisfaction which is countered with the threat of
castration.) The ego, originally motivated solely by the id and its quest for
libidinous pleasure, has been forced by reality to turn against the desires of the
id and to repress them. The super-ego is constituted by that moment of turning,
in which the Oedipus complex is overcome:
The
child's parents, and especially his father, were perceived as the obstacle to a
realization of his Oedipus wishes; so his infantile ego forti®ed itself for the
carrying out of the repression by erecting this same obstacle within itself. It
borrowed strength to do this, so to speak, from the father, and this loan was
an extraordinarily momentous act. The super-ego retains the character of the
father, while the more powerful the Oedipus complex was and the more rapidly it
succumbed to repression (under the influence of authority, religious teaching,
schooling and reading), the stricter will be the domination of the super-ego
over the ego later on - in the form of conscience or perhaps of an unconscious
sense of guilt. (11.374)
It is
because the super-ego ‘retains the character of the father' that it is no
longer the servant of the ego - the guardian of the threshold, the censor - but
its master:
Although
it is accessible to all later influences, it nevertheless preserves throughout
life the character given to it by its derivation from the father-complex —
namely, the capacity to stand apart from the ego and to master it. It is a memorial
of the former weakness and dependence of the ego, and the mature ego remains
subject to its domination. As the child was once under a compulsion to obey its
parents, so the ego submits to the categorical imperative of the super- eg°.
(11.389)
This ‘categorical
imperative’ is like the Kantian one in that it demands compliance irrespective
of inclination; it is unlike it in that it is not the self-imposed principle of
the autonomous rational will but a heteronomous demand that the ego is
compelled to internalize but that continues to stand over against it as the
demand of the other. The Freudian ‘genealogy of morals’ reveals that human
moral autonomy — whether in its Platonic, its Kantian or its Nietzschean form —
is an illusion.
A further question
arises at this point. ‘How is it that the super-ego manifests itself
essentially as a sense of guilt (or rather, as criticism — for the sense of
guilt is the perception in the ego answering to this criticism) and moreover
develops such extraordinary harshness and severity towards the ego?’ (11.394).
It seems that the super-ego redirects an aggressiveness originally directed
towards others against the ego itself; hence the harshness and cruelty even of
‘ordinary normal morality’ (11.396). This aggressiveness may be traced back to
the ‘death instinct’, which aims to lead organic life back into the inanimate
state, in contrast to the sexual instinct, or Eros, which aims at the
preservation of life. It is to be traced back not simply to the paternal
prohibition in itself but also to the aggressiveness that this prohibition
evokes in the child himself, which is then displaced onto the ego through
identihcation with the father. Torn between the hyper-moral severity of the
super-ego and the amorality of the id, the ego hnds itself in an unenviable
situation. ‘Helpless in both directions, the ego defends itself vainly, alike
against the instigations of the murderous id and against the reproaches of the
punishing conscience’ (11.395). The ego may well cry out: ‘Wretched man that I
am! Who will deliver me from this body of death?’ (Rom. 7.24). On Freud’s
reading of the situation, ‘The ego gives itself up because it feels itself
hated and persecuted by the super-ego, instead of being loved’ (11.400).
The introduction of
the concept of the super-ego results in a model of the psyche analogous to the
Pauline one in Romans 7. This analogy justihes an approach to Freud as a
‘reader’ of a Pauline text, whether or not he was himself familiar with
it.13 But
his ‘reading’ might proceed in one of two directions. He might argue that
psychoanalysis helps the ego to resist the super-ego’s harsh demands by
exposing its genealogy, that the particular form of the super-ego is merely a
cultural construct, and that the reconstruction or re-education of the
super-ego is therefore both desirable and possible. Since Freud’s modelling of
the psyche is inseparable from his account of sexuality, the outcome would be a
call for the liberalization of traditional sexual morality. In terms of the
Pauline text, this would be a
13 In Moses and Monotheism (1939),
Paul plays a crucial role in the transition from Judaism, the religion of the
father, to Christianity, the religion of the son. Freud’s Oedipus theory leads
him to postulate as the origin of culture and religion an event in which the
all-powerful father of the patriarchal horde is murdered by his sons — an event
re-enacted in the murder of Moses. Moses was an Egyptian, a follower of the
monotheistic Pharaoh Akhenaten, who led his supporters out of Egypt when the
priests of Aten succeeded in overturning the monotheistic reforms. The theory
that he was murdered is drawn from the Old Testament scholar Ernst Sellin, who
in 1922 'found in the prophet Hosea . . . unmistakable signs of a tradition to
the effect that Moses, the founder of their religion, met with a violent end in
a rising of his refractory and stiff-necked people, and that at the same time
the religion he had introduced was thrown off’ (13.275—6). His supporters
allied themselves with certain Midianite tribes, and the religion that arose at
Kadesh (enshrined in the Pentateuch) was a compromise between Moses’ monotheism
and the Midianites’ more primitive Yahwism. The result was a father-religion, a
return of the repressed, primal father after a period of matriarchy, in which
the ambivalence that is of the essence of the relation to the father was
denied. 'There was no place in the framework of the religion of Moses for a
direct expression of the murderous hatred of the father. All that could come to
light was a mighty reaction against it — a sense of guilt on account of that
hostility, a bad conscience for having sinned against God and for not ceasing
to sin’ (13.383). The ethical ideals of which Jews are so proud cannot 'disavow
their origin from the sense of guilt felt on account of a suppressed hostility
to God. They possess the characteristic ... of obsessional neurotic
reaction-formations; we can guess, too, that they serve the secret purposes of
punishment’ (13.383—4). It was Paul who first instinctively grasped that 'the
reason why we are so unhappy is that we have killed God the father’ (13.384).
Paul 'seized upon this sense of guilt and traced it back correctly to its
original source. He called this the ''original sin’’; it was a crime against God
and could only be atoned for by death . . . A son of God had allowed himself to
be killed without guilt and had thus taken on himself the guilt of all men. It
had to be a son, since it had been the murder of a father’ (13.330 — 1). Yet
the new religion was simply a restatement of the old problem. 'Its main content
was . . . reconciliation with God the Father, atonement for the crime committed
against him; but the other side of the emotional relation showed itself in the
fact that the son, who had taken the atonement on himself, became a god himself
beside the father and, actually, in place of the father. Christianity, having
arisen out of a father-religion, became a son-religion. It has not escaped the
fate of having to get rid of the father’ (13.385). Freud is dependent here on
the well-known claim (already exploited by Nietzsche) that Paul was the real
founder of Christianity. There is no sign of any knowledge of the Pauline
texts.
critical,
‘antinomian’ reading that taught the ego to distance itself from the super-ego
(‘the Law of God’) and to reappropriate the repressed forces of the id.
Alternatively, Freud might argue that his model of the psyche is the
presupposition of all particular cultural constructs, and that he has identihed
a conflict endemic to human existence as such. Pauline identification with the
demands of the super-ego, with the ensuing anxiety and guilt, would then
represent a moment of genuine insight. If ‘sexual liberation’ represents the
enticing promise of a restored, natural, prelapsarian sexuality, without
anxiety or guilt, this second Freudian reading of Paul would regard this
promise with a degree of scepticism.
THE LIMITS OF FREEDOM
Conventional
(or Christian) sexual morality, confining sexual activity to marriage, is
perhaps to be seen as a ‘cultural construct’, whose advantages and
disadvantages may be dispassionately weighed. If the disadvantages outweigh
the advantages - and the grounds for this judgment may seem to be strong —
then it can be modified or abandoned, giving way to new constructions in which
older prohibitions and limits become fluid and new sexualities proliferate
without shame or guilt. If there is an ‘enlightenment project’ in the field of
sexuality, it consists in the critique of Christian sexual morality in the name
of an open, unrepressed discourse on ‘sex’ and in the corresponding practices
of ‘sexual liberation’. If there is a ‘postmodern’ account of sexuality, it
will emphasize the plurality of sexualities, seen now as the products of
culture rather than as biological or natural imperatives. Yet the differences
here between enlightenment and postmodernism are less striking than the
continuities: they agree in their rejection of the single, monopolistic sexual
morality supposedly inherited from the Christian past, they agree that new
sexualities are possible and desirable, and they agree that the burden of guilt
must be replaced by the innocence of play. The question is whether and how far
Freud endorses the project of ‘sexual liberation’; whether and how far he is
the prophet or father of ‘sex’, as it is now construed, or whether he belongs
within a ‘critique of sex’.
Freud can indeed see
sexual morality as a ‘cultural construct’ open to development and modihcation.
In the first of the Three Essays on Sexuality (1905), he asserts that
the boundary between ‘normal’ and ‘abnormal’ sexual behaviour may be a matter
of convention:
The
use of the mouth as a sexual organ is regarded as a perversion if the lips (or
tongue) of one person are brought into contact with the genitals of another,
but not if the mucous membranes of the lips of both of them come together. This
exception is the point of contact with what is normal. Those who condemn the
other practices (which have no doubt been common among mankind from primaeval
times) as being perversions, are giving way to an unmistakable feeling of disgust,
which protects them from accepting sexual aims of the kind. The limits of such
disgust are, however, often purely conventional: a man who will kiss a pretty
girl’s lips passionately may perhaps be disgusted at the idea of using her
toothbrush, though there are no grounds for supposing that his own oral cavity,
for which he feels no disgust, is any cleaner than the girl’s. (7.63-4)
Certain
sexual practices are rejected purely because they are found to be ‘disgusting’,
not because there are any rational grounds for condemning them. This disgust is
a matter of local convention, and cannot be traced back to any universal ‘human
nature’. The young man feels disgust at the thought of using the girl’s
toothbrush because he was taught as a child that his toothbrush is for his use
only and that he in turn must not use the toothbrushes of other family members
(even if he rinses them carefully before and after use). Implements such as
forks and spoons come into contact with his ‘oral cavity’ without any such
convention of exclusive ownership, and the arbitrariness of these oral
conventions illustrates the difficulty of differentiating ‘natural’ or ‘normal’
sexual practices from ‘unnatural’ or ‘deviant’ ones.
The conventional
character of sexual morality is, for Freud, also indicated by the factor of
social class. Take the case of a middle-class child who engages in sexual games
with the caretaker’s daughter, who ‘would have had an opportunity of observing
a good deal of adult sexuality’:
These
experiences, even if they were not continued over a long period, would be
enough to set certain sexual impulses to work in the two children; and, after
their games together had ceased, these impulses would for several years
afterwards ®nd expression in masturbation. So much for their experiences in
common; the ®nal outcome in the two children will be very different . . . [The
caretaker's daughter] will go through her life undamaged by the early exercise
of her sexuality and free from neurosis. With the landlord's little girl things
will be different. At an early stage and while she is still a child she will
get an idea that she has done something wrong; after a short time, but perhaps
only after a severe struggle, she will give up her masturbatory satisfaction,
but she will nevertheless still have some sense of oppression about her. When
in her later girlhood she is in a position to learn something of human sexual
intercourse, she will turn away from it with unexplained disgust and prefer to
remain in ignorance . . . [Thus] it will turn out that the well-brought-up,
intelligent and high-minded girl has completely repressed her sexual impulses,
but that these, unconscious to her, are still attached to her petty experiences
with her childhood friend. (1.3p8±9)
Here, an
analysis of sexuality as a social construct shades over into critique:
conventional middle-class sexual morality all too easily deprives its victims
(especially its female victims) of the possibility of sexual ful®lment. It
tends to produce a disabling disgust not simply at sexual deviancy but at
‘normal’ sexual intercourse. As the result of its strictures, the trivial
sexual explorations of childhood can assume a disproportionate significance.
The straightforwardness of the caretaker’s daughter is proof that all this need
not be the case, and that it is possible to go through life regarding sexual
activity as ‘natural and harmless’. Yet Freud does not wish to deprive the
middle-class girl of her ‘higher moral and intellectual development’ (1.399);
he does not suggest that she should be given the same opportunities to observe
adult sexual activity as the caretaker’s daughter. If there are lessons to be
learned from this cautionary tale, they represent only minor modifications to
the status quo: adults, we might conclude, should be more tolerant towards the
sexuality of childhood and should inculcate in their children an awareness of
(marital) sexuality as natural and good, not a cause for shame. Freud himself
does not draw even these modest conclusions, since he is more interested in
subjecting sexual neuroses to psychoanalytic treatment than in advocating any
particular reforms to the sexual code.
On occasion, Freud
does campaign actively for change. In a paper entitled ‘“Civilized” Sexual
Morality and Modern Nervous Illness’ (Die “kulturelle” Sexualmoral und die
moderne Nervo- sitat [1908]), he poses the question ‘whether sexual
intercourse in legal marriage can offer full compensation for the restriction
imposed before marriage’, and ®nds ‘an abundance of material supporting a reply
in the negative’ (12.46). If satisfying sexual intercourse within marriage is
achieved at all, it will last only for a few years; and it may never be achieved,
since the girl who has been kept in a state of sexual ignorance prior to
marriage ‘has nothing but disappointments to offer the man who has saved up all
his desire for her’ (12.50). ‘To the uninitiated it is hardly credible how
seldom normal potency is to be found in a husband and how often a wife is
frigid among married couples who live under the dominance of our civilized
sexual morality, what a degree of renunciation, often on both sides, is
entailed by marriage, and to what narrow limits married life — the happiness
that is so ardently desired — is narrowed down’ (12.53).
It is medical
science (and not psychoanalysis as such) that here lends its prestige to the
campaign for reforming sexual morality. It is true that medical opinion is
divided on this issue: the opposing view, ‘that sexual abstinence is not
harmful and not dif®cult to maintain, has also been widely supported by the
medical profession’ (12.45). But the view that sexual abstinence and repression
endanger mental health is not a speci®cally psychoanalytical doctrine. As the
opening pages of Freud’s paper explicitly indicate, his twin themes of
conventional sexual morality and nervous illness (or ‘neurasthenia’) are
well-known current topoi; his assertion of a causal connection between
the two will hardly have seemed untoward in the pages of a journal entitled Sexual-Probleme,
and he asserts this connection simply as a ‘physician’ (12.34) and not in the
name of psychoanalysis. In this paper, psychoanalysis aligns itself with a
pre-existing discourse on sexuality and sexual reform, in much the same way as
Freud will later align himself with a pre-existing ideology of science in his
critique of religion as ‘illusion’. This explains how an English translation of
1915 could in 1931 be reprinted as a pamphlet by ‘Eugenics Publications, New
York’, and thus assimilated to a eugenicist discourse essentially alien to
psychoanalysis. Psychoanalysis lends its weight to an existing discourse, and
in turn avails itself of the power and prestige of that discourse; but in the
process its own most characteristic features are temporarily set aside.
When Freud addresses
the question of conventional sexual morality as a psychoanalyst, the outcome is
rather different. Towards the end of the Introductory Lectures of
1915-17, he rhetorically imputes to his audience the view that psychoanalysis
helps its patients by encouraging them to disregard conventional moral
boundaries in their quest for sexual fulhlment. In fact, nothing could be
further from the truth:
A
recommendation to the patient to ‘live a full life’ sexually could not possibly
play a part in analytic therapy — if only because we ourselves have declared
that an obstinate conflict is taking place in him between a libidinal impulse
and sexual repression, between a sensual and an ascetic trend. This conflict
would not be solved by our helping one of these trends to victory over its
opponent. We see, indeed, that in neurotics asceticism has the upper hand; and
the consequence of this is precisely that the suppressed sexual tendency ®nds a
way out in symptoms. If, on the contrary, we were to secure victory for
sensuality, then the sexual repression that had been put on one side would
necessarily be replaced by symptoms. Neither of these two alternative decisions
could end the internal conflict; in either case one party to it would remain
unsatisfied. (1.483—4)
Psychoanalysis
is not in favour of conventional virtue, but it eschews the role of mentor and
leaves the patient to make his own decisions. Above all, it emphasizes the
severe constraints within which any modification of existing sexual practice
must take place. The ego is suspended between the conflicting demands of
super-ego and id, and although it may take certain measures to ease its
situation it cannot rid itself of the tension. The optimistic assumptions that
sex is natural, good and enjoyable, that repression is bad, and that these
facts can straightforwardly be translated into harmonious and innocent sexual
practice, are alien to Freud.
Paradoxically, it is
the non-psychoanalytic Freud — the Freud who participates in the campaign
against sexual ignorance and repression — who corresponds most closely to the
‘Freud’ of the general imagination. This image of Freud locates him at the
turning-point between a nineteenth century in which sex was hypocritically
repressed and a twentieth century in which sex has been rehabilitated as
natural, good and enjoyable. This ‘Freud’ plays a key role in what Foucault has
identihed and criticized as ‘the repressive hypothesis’ that has shaped the
modern discourse on sex. ‘Until Freud’, it is said, ‘the discourse on sex . . .
never ceased to hide the things it was speaking about’ (History of
Sexuality, 1.53); but after Freud, sex was able to speak freely, naming
itself as ‘sex’. Thus sex comes to be spoken of with evangelical earnestness.
According to Foucault:
A
great sexual sermon — which has had its subtle theologians and its popular
voices — has swept through our societies over the last decades; it has
chastised the old order, denounced hypocrisy, and praised the rights of the
immediate and the real; it has made people dream of a New City. (1.7—8)
It
is certainly legitimate to ask why sex was associated with sin for such a long
time — although it would remain to be discovered how this association was
formed, and one would have to be careful not to state in a summary and hasty
fashion that sex was ‘condemned’ — but we must also ask why we burden ourselves
today with so much guilt for having once made sex a sin. What paths have
brought us to the point where we are ‘at fault’ with respect to our own sex?
And how have we come to be a civilization so peculiar as to tell itself that,
through an abuse of power which has not ended, it has long ‘sinned’ against
sex? How does one account for the displacement which, while claiming to free us
from the sinful nature of sex, taxes us with a great historical wrong which
consists precisely in imagining that nature to be blameworthy and in drawing
disastrous consequences from that belief? (1.9)
For
Foucault, in opposition to the ‘repressive hypothesis’, the issue is no longer
‘to determine whether one says yes or no to sex, whether one formulates
prohibitions or per missions, whether one asserts its importance or denies its
effects . . . ’ (1.11). The aim is to investigate ‘the way in which sex is “put
into discourse’’’, irrespective of ‘whether these discursive productions and
these effects of power lead one to formulate the truth about sex, or on the
contrary falsehoods designed to conceal that truth’ (1.11 — 12). But one might
also investigate the way in which ‘Freud’ is put into discourse, and so
discover the extent to which this discourse conceals precisely that ‘truth
about sex’ that Freud himself sought to uncover.
The insertion of
Freud into the ‘repressive hypothesis’ serves to marginalize the distinctive
content of the psychoanalytic discourse on sex. On this view, what occurs in
Freud is simply that, having previously been silent, sex now speaks — it speaks
itself, it calls itself by its proper name, ‘sex’, in token of the fact that
reticence, shame and guilt are banished and innocence restored. ‘Freud’ is
this speech-event; his discourse is the speech-act in which sex names itself
and closes the era of silence. The specihc content of this speech-act is not
entirely unknown. That repression causes neurotic symptoms is a Freudian
doctrine that the repressive hypothesis can readily make its own, enabling it
to assert the superiority of modern, unrepressed sex over ‘Victorian hypocrisy’
with all the selfrighteousness of the pharisee towards the tax-collector. But
the Freudian doctrine that repression is an inescapable fact of human existence
is passed over in silence. This doctrine challenges the repressive hypothesis
at its core. By complicating the simple story of a passage from one sexual
regime to another, it disturbs its complacency; and it must therefore be
repressed.[xliii]
If, as Freud argues,
the ego is constituted by the opposition between super-ego and id, and if this
opposition is ultimately indissoluble, whatever adjustments may perhaps be
possible and desirable, then human sexuality is irreducibly complex. Freudian
theory asserts this complexity in opposition not to ‘Victorian hypocrisy’ or
‘Christianity’s negative attitude towards the body’ but to the modern,
enlightened discourse of sexual liberation. Itself implicated in that
discourse, it deconstructs it. The difference between the Freudian project and
the project of sexual enlightenment is the difference between a Pauline model
of the person as the site of the conflict between super-ego and id, law and
flesh, and a ‘liberal’ model of the person as a property owner whose freedom in
relation to the body is limited only by the property rights of others. Fundamental
to the Freudian view of the person is the reality of‘guilt’, which, as the
subjective byproduct of objective structures of human existence, can more
readily be seen as symptomatic of ‘sin’ than dismissed as an illusion created
by a merely contingent repression. ‘Sin’, of course, requires a theological
framework that Freud regards as no longer tenable in the age of science. But
his own ‘scientific’ framework is still recognizably modelled on that older
theological framework, especially in its Pauline-Augustinian form — just as the
liberal view is modelled on the Pelagian view of the person as endowed with a
purely neutral freedom limited only by the rights of others (notably God,
although the liberal version of the Pelagian picture will discover that it has
no need of that hypothesis).
Freud makes
comprehensible again Augustine’s understanding of concupiscence as ‘the lust
which lords it over the unchaste, has to be mastered by the chaste, and yet is
to be blushed at by the chaste and the unchaste’ (De nuptiis et concupiscentia,
ii.59). For Augustine’s Pelagian opponents, sexuality evokes no such
ambivalence; there is no need to connect it with blushing. The ‘vigour of the
members’ is cause for celebration not shame, even though it is beyond the
control of the will. This involuntary erectile potency would surely have
flourished in Paradise, for Paradise is its birthplace and home. There, ‘it
would always have been exercised and never repressed, lest so great a pleasure
should ever be denied to so happy an estate . . . And so, should the motion of
lust precede men’s will, then the will would immediately follow it’ (ii.59).
But that is to project present sexual experience back into Paradise, thereby
idealizing and mythologizing it by investing it with the innocent wonder of the
®rst man and woman, who knew only of a pristine existence that unambiguously
expressed the goodness of the Creator. In this Pelagian sex, Paradise is
restored as a man and a woman are drawn by their desire for one another into
the shared joy of sexual union. But for Augustine, there is discontinuity as
well as continuity between the sexual experience of the present and of
Paradise. That which the Creator intended has been overlaid by the human
decision to establish an autonomous good and evil and by the ensuing judgment,
which subjected human life to the anonymous power of a concupiscence in which
excess, shame and violence have marred the original joy. Within marriage, and
through the divine grace, something of the original joy at sharing in the work
of creation may still be present. Yet even here, the clearest symptoms of shame
persist. Augustine mentions just one of these symptoms: blushing, the
visible, physiological manifestation of shame. Blushing occurs when the
intention of concealment is overtaken by an accident: a careless turn of
phrase, a lapse of discretion, the intrusion of a third party, an exposure of
flesh. If the truth about ‘sex’ is simple — that it is natural, good and
enjoyable, nothing to be ashamed of — then it is not clear why these utterly
trivial events should evoke such profound discomfort.
Like Augustine,
Freud regards such familiar but opaque phenomena as symptoms of a forgotten
world of complexities and ambivalences. It is the knowledge of this world that
the discourse of ‘sex’ strives to repress. The Freudian ‘hermeneutic of
suspicion’ might diagnose in this repression a ruse of the ego. The ego ‘is not
only helper to the id; it is also a submissive slave who courts his master’s
love. Whenever possible, it tries to remain on good terms with the id; it
clothes the id’s Ucs. commands with its Pcs. rationalizations; it
pretends that the id is showing obedience to the admonitions of reality, even
when in fact it is remaining obstinate and unyielding; it disguises the id’s
conflicts with reality and, if possible, with the super-ego too’ (11.398).
‘Sex’, we might say, is the product of just such a false consciousness. It is
the ego’s attempt to conceal the conflicts between id and reality by
interposing an ideological screen, onto which is projected the fantasy-reality
of the erotic Paradise. At the risk of seeming too 'negative about sex', it is
the Pauline model of an ego torn by the conflict between law and flesh that can
restore the reality that 'sex' represses.
CHAPTER
FOUR
In the
Freudian model of the self, Paul’s portrayal of the ego as torn between the
demands of law and flesh reappears in twentieth-century guise. The old language
has been modernized, fitting it for a new career within a twentieth-century
discourse on sex whose repeated announcements of a turningpoint between the
old era and the new it effectively subverts. Yet, if within Freud’s texts there
occurs a ‘reading’ of a Pauline text, this is clearly also a misreading.
Little or nothing survives of the context in which the Pauline language has its
natural habitat. That is of course deliberate: Freud’s texts are resolute in
their rejection of the ‘illusion’ on whose stories and traditions they continue
to draw. But if we do not reject those stories and traditions, if we continue
to regard them as embodying truth rather than illusion, the relationship of the
ancient and the modern texts will be reversed. Paul will no longer be the
precursor of Freud - a source for certain of his conceptual moves, apparently
unrecognized by Freud himself or by his interpreters. Instead, Freud will be
the precursor of Paul. A reading of Freud as subverting the discourse of sexual
liberation is already a Pauline (and Augustinian) reading of Freud; and perhaps
also — at least on some criteria — a misreading. The intention of this reading
was to problematize the assumption that a negative, Christian attitude towards
sex and the body has now at last been replaced by a positive one, and that this
is all to the good. Freud is precursor to Paul in the sense that he may help to
overcome some of the almost insuperable prejudices that prevent Pauline
statements on sexuality from being heard. But in the end it is Paul (and not
Freud) who must be heard — insofar as he is acknowledged within the Christian
community as an 'apostle of Jesus Christ' whose texts lie close to the centre
of Christian canonical scripture. He is not to be heard simply as 'Paul' but,
in accordance with his own self-designation, as 'Paul, a slave of Christ Jesus,
called to be an apostle, set apart for the gospel of God' (Rom. 1.1). In this
setting apart for the gospel of God there is also a setting apart from a merely
individual 'Paul', some of whose personal idiosyncrasies may still be traced in
his texts. What must be heard - if it can be heard - is the apostolic testimony
to the gospel of God as it touches and transforms the sphere of sexuality and
the body.
SPIRIT AND LETTER [VERSES I -6)
Or
are you unaware, brothers [and sisters] -for I speak to those who know the law
- that the law exercises authority over a person only as long as he lives? (Rom. 7.1) We enter
the discourse when it is already in full flow, and must begin by orienting
ourselves. Who is addressed here? How are we who overhear related to these
primary addressees? What has the theme of the discourse to do with us?
The discourse is
addressed 'to all who are in Rome, God's beloved, called to be saints' (1.7),
and it is addressed to them by one whose commission is to bring about 'the
obedience of faith among all the Gentiles, for the sake of his name, among whom
you too are called by Jesus Christ' (1.5-6). The particular addressees -
Gentile Christians in Rome - are enclosed within the much wider category of'all
the Gentiles'; they are addressed as belonging to that category and as
representative of it. But it is therefore 'all the Gentiles' who are themselves
indirectly addressed, in the person of their representatives in first-century
Rome. The address to a particular group of persons is not a limiting of the
writer's universal commission; it is not a tacit admission that the abstract
notion of a universal commission is unworkable in practice, and that the real
commission is simply to the local groups that spring up in various places. The
apostle's right to address those who are in Rome is in fact dependent on his
universal commission to bring about the obedience of faith among all the
Gentiles. It is on the basis of this commission that he addresses them, and
this gives his address its comprehensive significance. He speaks to the Roman
Christians not as private individuals or as members of purely local
communities, but as particular representatives of the universal scope of the
divine address to humankind embodied in Jesus and his Spirit. As Paul himself
is not a private individual but represents that universal scope in his own
person, so it is with his addressees. They are ‘in Rome’, but what is more
important is that they belong to a wider group of people who are ‘called by
Jesus Christ’ (1.6), who themselves represent the universal sphere of ‘all the
Gentiles’ — ‘Greeks and barbarians, wise and foolish’ (1.14). The scope of
Paul’s testimony also extends into the future; by means of the written text, he
continues to ful®l his commission to bring about the obedience of faith long
after his death. It is not a mere accident of history that we are in a position
to overhear Paul’s discourse to the Romans, for the text itself intends a
readership as broad as the apostolic commission — or rather, as broad as the
grace of God in Jesus Christ, the basis for the apostolic commission.[xliv]
It is ‘brothers’ who
are addressed in Romans 7.1. That adelphoi ‘includes’ adelphai is
clear from the many greetings to women as well as men in Romans 16: those who
are commended for their work in the Lord can hardly have been excluded from the
circle of the letter’s addressees. A commission to ‘all the Gentiles’ includes
women as well as men within its scope. The addressees are ‘brothers and
sisters’ on the basis of Jesus’ saying: ‘Whoever does the will of God is my
brother, my sister and mother’ (Mk. 3.35). Jesus, the Son of God, is ‘the
®rst-born of many brothers [and sisters]’ (Rom. 8.29), who through him and with
him address God as ‘Abba, Father’ (8.15).
They have not always
been children of God, brothers and sisters of Jesus and of one another, but
have previously been characterized as those who have experienced a moment of
sharp discontinuity in their lives (Rom. 6). Behind them lies a transition from
one way of life to another, and they are exhorted to preserve this difference
from every encroachment of the old patterns of conduct. ‘Just as you once
subjected your bodily members to uncleanness and to every kind of lawless
conduct, so now subject your bodily members to righteousness, for holiness’
(6.19). The Christian brothers and sisters addressed in chapter 7 are said to
‘know the law’, but they also know what it is to devote their bodies to the
service of ‘uncleanness’ (akatharsia). Akatharsia is the conduct of
those who ‘dishonour their bodies among themselves’ (1.24), and is closely
associated with porneia, sexual immorality (Gal. 5.19, 2 Cor. 12.21).
The body that is dishonoured in akatharsia is therefore the body as
subject and object of sexual union - the body under the primacy of the
genitals, the ‘bodily members’ that acquire a privileged role in the service of
akatharsia and porneia, in the pursuit of sex. If their maleness
and femaleness now takes the form of a relationship between brothers and
sisters, that has not always been the case. In their different ways, they once
shared in a sexual culture that led them to do things of which, in the light of
the new teaching they have received, they are now ashamed (Rom. 6.21). And they
still live in the midst of the allurements of the sexual culture they have
rejected. It has not rejected them. It continues to offer itself to them as a
real possibility - perhaps even a Christian possibility. If we are under grace
and not under law, what is ‘sin’ (cf. 6.1, 15)? Paul himself states that ‘where
there is no law there is no transgression’ (4.15), and that ‘sin is not
reckoned where there is no law’. ‘Transgression’ and ‘sin’ are no more: under
grace, it seems, a whole moral vocabulary has been erased. Under grace, in the
absence of the harsh, condemning, moralizing law, might the joy of bodily union
not be a sacramental expression of the Christian’s union with Christ? Might
grace not permit what the law forbids?2 Whatever
their past relationship to the surrounding sexual culture, Paul’s readers
still ®nd themselves addressed by it in the present.
They are indeed
under grace, not law. ‘The grace of God and the gift in grace of the one man
Jesus Christ have abounded for many’ (5.15). Grace marks the limit of the law:
‘Law came in, so that the trespass might increase, but where sin increased
grace was all the more abundant’ (5.20). At the beginning of chapter 7, too,
the theme is the limit of the law: the law exercises authority over a person
only during his or her lifetime. But as yet this notion of a life lived ‘not
under law but under grace’ is opaque. What is it that motivates this
disjunction? Is it merely a pragmatic response to contingent problems in the
early church,
2 Such arguments may take various forms,
as three modern examples illustrate.
(1) Although the Christian view
of 'sex’ has always tended towards 'legalism’, Jesus himself 'boldly rejected
all such legalisms’, and endorses the view that 'whether any form of sex . . .
is good or evil depends on whether love is fully served’ ( Joseph Fletcher, Situation
Ethics, London: SCM Press, 1966, 139). This opposition between situational
love and legalistic morality is an attempt to radicalize the Pauline-
Augustinian antithesis of grace and law. Its motto is Augustine’s dilige et
quod vis,fac (79). (2) According to William Countryman, 'the demands of the
gospel of grace are being constantly renewed and ®tted to new situations by the
Spirit who animates the church’ (Dirt, Greed and Sex: Sexual Ethics in the
New Testament and their Implications for Today, Philadelphia: Fortress
Press, 1988, 239). Just as 'the New Testament rejected the imposition of the
purity codes of the Torah on Gentile Christians’, so today 'a Christian sexual
ethic that remains true to its New Testament roots will have to discard its
insistence on physical purity’ (243). 'Purity’ stands for the belief that 'a
given sexual act is wrong in and of itself’ (241), and is opposed by an ethic
of'sexual property’ in which 'the individual is the primary arbiter of his or her
sexual acts’ (242). (3) In sexual love, one’s sexual partner is 'the sacrament
of God’s joy, beauty and self-giving, the other as the sacrament of celebration
... [I]n the deepest forms of sexual encounter there is a holiness, that is a
purity and depth of recognition of the other, which speaks of the presence of
the holy God’ (T. J. Gorringe, Discerning Spirit: A Theology of Revelation,
London: SCM Press, 1990, 101 — 2). This is a distinctively Christian view, for
'only Christian doctrine teaches that the divine can be not merely immanent or
symbolized by material bodies but actually enfleshed, and only this doctrine
could make such an articulation of experience permissible and therefore
possible’ (99 — 100). Although the ideal of lifelong commitment is to be
respected, we must respond theologically to the fact that 'we may ''fall in
love’’ not once but several times’ — an experience 'which always comes to us as
a ''given’’ and with the power of revelation’ (106). To reject this experience
in its full sexual expression 'will seem to those involved like the sin against
the Holy Spirit, calling that which is good evil’ (106).
or does
it articulate something that is basic to Christian living as such? According to
Augustine, ‘the law was given that grace might be sought; grace was given that
the law might be fulhlled’ (De spiritu et littera, 34). ‘The law says:
Thou shalt not desire. Faith says: Heal my soul, for I have sinned against
thee. Grace says: Behold, thou art made whole; sin no more, lest a worse thing befall
thee’ (52).3 On that view, living under grace rather than law
cannot be reduced to Gentile Christians’ freedom from the obligation to
practise Judaism. The ‘law’ that the antithesis excludes is the demand, ‘Thou
shalt . . . ’ or ‘Thou shalt not. . . ’, insofar as it presupposes a free moral
agent as its addressee. Grace closes off that apparent possibility. It is ‘the
Spirit of life in Christ Jesus’ (Rom. 8.2) who establishes the human freedom to
live in conformity to the will of God. Under this regime, the body is ‘a living
sacrihce, holy and acceptable to God’ (12.1), and is no longer oriented towards
akatharsia.4
3 In this chapter, translations from
Augustine are adapted from The Nicene and Post- Nicene Fathers: St
Augustine, vols. i, iii, v (repr. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1971—9). In the
case of the Confessions, I have also drawn on the translations of R. S.
Pine-Coffin (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1961), and H. Chadwick (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1991).
4 Here and elsewhere in this chapter, my
use of Augustine as a Pauline interpreter is in reaction against recent
attempts to replace the Augustinian-Lutheran reading of Paul with a ‘new
perspective’, which emphasizes the irreducibility of the Jew—Gentile issues
Paul faced to any more 'abstract’ or 'universal’ theological problematic. (My
earlier book, Paul, Judaism and the Gentiles, is itself an exercise in
that genre.) In Augustine, it is said, 'the Pauline thought about the Law and
Justi®cation was applied in a consistent and grand style to a more general and
timeless human problem’ (K. Stendahl, 'Paul and the Introspective Conscience of
the West’ [1963], repr. in his Paul among Jews and Gentiles,
Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1976, 78—96; 85). Paul’s own concern was simply
with 'the place of the Gentiles in the Church and in the plan of God’ (84). In
Rom. 7 — a crucially important text for the so-called 'introspective conscience
of the west’ — a commonplace observation about the goodness of the law and the
wickedness of sin 'appeared to later interpreters to be a most penetrating
insight into the nature of man and into the nature of sin’ (93). Along similar
lines, S. Stowers argues that Augustine 'internalized, individualized, and
generalized such Pauline concepts as justification, sin, law, works, salvation,
and election’ (A Rereading of Romans: Justice, Jews and Gentiles, New
Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1994, 13 — 14). He 'developed a way of
understanding the gospel and of reading Romans that made the Jew the
archetypical sinner and rebel against God’s grace’ (13). With due respect to
Augustine and others, 'the historian of early Christian literature must imagine
what it would be like to come upon Romans for the ®rst time’, and read it 'as a
writing of antiquity’, unencumbered by 'the purposes of the theologians and
churchmen’ (4). As for Rom. 7, Paul here uses the rhetorical device of prosopopoeia
or speech-in-character to construct a ®ctional Gentile convert to Judaism, who
confesses For
the married woman is bound by law to her husband as long as he lives; but if
the husband dies, she is freed from the law of the husband. (v. 2) A
slippage occurs between the first two sentences of the chapter. Initially it
was said that the law is binding only during a person’s lifetime, but now a law
is specified that binds one party only during the lifetime of another. The
general principle, that death marks the limit of the law’s jurisdiction, is
illustrated by a case in which the death of one marks the termination of the
law’s jurisdiction over another. The slippage is necessary to the theological
position for which these general analogies prepare the ground: for to be ‘under
grace’ is to be subject not only to a negation (a death) but also to an
affirmation (a life beyond that death). To be under grace is to re-enact in
daily conduct the pattern of Jesus’ death and resurrection, in the negation of
one mode of being and the af®rmation of another that this pattern entails. The
®gure of the cruci®ed and risen Jesus is already dimly discernible in the
husband who dies and in the wife who survives him. ‘Christ who has been raised
from the dead dies no more, death no longer has dominion over him. As for his
death, he died to sin, once for all; as for his life, he lives to God’
(6.9—10). This is the pattern re-enacted in the Christian life: ‘So you too
must regard yourselves as dead to sin and alive to God in Christ Jesus’ (6.11).
It is,
then, the Christian who — following the pattern of Christ — is both the husband
who dies and the wife who lives. That which is negated is the self apart from
the grace of God, an abstraction that may have had a biographical counterpart
in a life prior to conversion but that may also be understood in non-
chronological terms as an alter ego or shadow that accompanies
one on one’s way, that bears one’s own form, and that represents the enduring
possibility of a selfhood on which the light that Paul encountered on the
Damascus Road does not shine. The imperative, ‘Regard yourselves as dead
to sin . . . ’, already
his difficulties with the
practice of the law; the intention is to dissuade Gentiles from conversion to
Judaism (264—84). Stendahl and Stowers show both that 'the historian’ can
indeed offer certain clarifications of the Pauline texts, and that hostility to
their theological appropriation leads rapidly to banal and superficial
exegesis. implies
a possible ‘mode of being oneself’ in which one fails to live in the light of
the divine negation and affirmation but seeks out a quite different orientation
by which to live — turning away from the light and finding one’s self in the
shadow. The divine negation and affirmation that occurs in Jesus’ death and
resurrection has put this shadow definitively behind us. The divine act
differentiates the ‘husband’ who belongs to the past from the ‘wife’ who now
lives apart from the husband; it forbids any attempt at a reunion in which the
two again become ‘one flesh’. It was once said: ‘What God has joined let no one
separate’ (Matt. 19.6). The woman was bound by law to her husband. But now it
is said: What God has separated let no one join. The woman is freed from the
law of the husband. As God once separated light from darkness, so he has
separated the self that is under grace from the self that seeks to exist apart
from grace.
If,
during her husband's lifetime, she joins herself to another man, she will be
regarded as an adulteress; but if her husband dies, she is free from the law,
so that she is not an adulteress if she joins herself to another man. (v. 3) There are two
situations in which the woman can join herself to another man: illicitly,
during her husband’s lifetime, and lawfully, after his death. Christ’s death is
the divine judgment of a world which the law proved unable to restore to its
proper subjection to God, and his life is the divine creation of a new world in
which humankind attains its appointed telos in union with Christ. After
her husband’s death, the woman must join herself to another man rather than
remain single: for Christ ‘died for all so that those who live might no longer
live for themselves but for him who for their sake died and was raised’ (2 Cor.
5.15). Yet there are those for whom the law is the ®nal, de®nitive divine
address to humankind, and who believe humankind to be de®nitively constituted
by this divine address. From their standpoint, the woman remains bound by the
law of the husband, and the Pauline proclamation of grace sounds very much like
an incitement to ‘adultery’. There is a general belief in Jerusalem that Paul
teaches ‘all the Jews who are among the Gentiles to forsake Moses, telling them
not to circumcise their children or observe the customs’ (Acts 21.21). He
teaches unfaithfulness to the God of the fathers; and instead of instructing
Gentiles in the Torah, he teaches them to do evil that good may come (Rom.
3.8). The Christian who joins herself to Christ because a death has occurred
that frees her from the law will appear to be an ‘adulteress’ to those who do
not recognize in the event of that death the divine judgment of the world.5
The issue here is
not simply that of a ‘Jewish identity’, symbolized by the ‘boundary-markers’
that most visibly differentiate Jews from Gentiles. Earlier in Romans, Paul
has addressed a fictional Jewish teacher (perhaps based in part on his own
pre-Christian past) who understands himself to be ‘a guide to the blind, a
light to those in darkness, an instructor of the ignorant, a teacher of
children’ — on the basis not of his own wisdom and insight but of the divine
law, in which he ®nds ‘the embodiment of knowledge and truth’ (2.17—20). On
this basis, Gentiles as well as Jews are taught to discern the divine will:
they are not to steal, commit adultery or worship idols (2.21—2). They are to
live henceforth in a de-divinized, demythologized world, subject only to the
divine categorical imperative. This mode of living is proper to them, as
rational and moral agents created by God, and since it is proper to them it is
also possible for them. This proclamation evokes immediate echoes in a world
which is already not wholly ignorant of ‘the decree of God’ (1.32), even prior
to the proclamation. If in this proclamation ‘Jewish identity’ is at stake,
that identity consists not
5 Throughout the discussion, I assume
that the illustrations in vv. 1—3 can be fully integrated into the argument of
vv. 4—6. This is in line with Karl Barth’s interpretation, in which the
addressees of Rom. 7 are identi®ed with both the husband and the wife. In 7.1,
'the living man to whom Paul is referring, who is therefore subject to the law,
is man “in the flesh’’ (7.5), who therefore lives as “the old man’’ (6.6) ...
In 7.2 a parable commences. As long as this man — the husband, it now says — is
alive, his wife is tied to him by the law which binds him — and which, as long
he is alive, binds her as well. In other words, as long as we (the husband)
live in the flesh as that old man, and we (the wife) are governed by the law
that binds him and therefore ourselves, we are in fact bound to become sinners
properly speaking because of the law and to be accused as such by the law . . .
Inasmuch as by the death of the old man we have been placed in a new situation,
we are then no longer bound by that necessity: then the law has lost for us its
power as instigator and accuser of our sin’ (A Shorter Commentary on Romans
[1956], ET London: 1959, 77—8). I do not understand why C. E. B. Cranfield
rejects this interpretation as 'extremely complicated and forced’ (Romans
I-VIII, International Critical Commentary, Edinburgh: T & T Clark,
1975, 1.334). simply
in the distinctive pattern of life that binds a particular ethnic group
together but in the vocation to bear witness among the nations to the will of
the one true God. It is on the basis of that unique vocation that the teacher
of the law ‘calls himself a Jew’ (2.17). He contributes to the formation of a
Judaeo-Christian tradition’ whose ‘ethical principles’ are said — most
forcefully by Nietzsche — still to permeate the political- ethical discourse of
modernity.
The
dignity and majesty of the divine law appears to ensure the dignity and majesty
of its human addressee. The human existence that sees itself as subject to the
law’s categorical imperative is an unbroken existence. It has not been
crucihed, nor has it been raised from the dead. From this standpoint, the idea
that human life should be shaped by the pattern of Jesus’ death and
resurrection is simply another aberration of religious enthusiasm. Those who
are seduced by it are unfaithful to the God in whose command humans approach
most nearly to the mysterious constitution of reality-itself.
So,
my brothers [and sisters], you too died to the law through the body of Christ,
so that you might belong to another, to him who has been raised from the dead
so that we might bear fruit for God. (v. 4) Reality-itself is in
fact to be found in the rupturing and remaking of human existence in Jesus’
death and resurrection. ‘You died’: the readers are identihed with the
‘husband’ of verses 2—3, who is also the ‘man’ of verse 1. To ‘die to the law’
is to leave the sphere of the law’s jurisdiction, as verse 1 has explained. ‘So
that you might belong to another’: the readers are also identi- hed with the
‘wife’ of verses 2—3, set free to remarry by her husband’s death. The crucihed
Christ identihes himself with a human existence subject to the judgment of God;
the risen Christ brings into being a new, fruitful human existence under the
grace of God. Identifying himself with the hrst ‘husband’ in his death, he
becomes the second ‘husband’ in his resurrection. The point of this language is
not to ‘legitimate patriarchal marriage’. It is rather to use whatever language
and conceptuality is to hand in order to articulate a relationship that is sui
generis and therefore beyond the scope of all such language and
conceptuality: the relationship between Jesus Christ and those who are in
Christ. This is an asymmetrical relationship in which one partner is
acknowledged by the other as ‘Lord’, and the then-current conception of
marriage as an asymmetrical relationship is therefore integral to the imagery.
The woman is said to be hypandros, under man’s authority (v. 2). Yet
there is no intention to affirm a particular conception of marriage, for it is
not the marriage of man and woman but the relation of Christ and the Christian
that is at issue.6
As in
marriage, Christian life is centred on personal relationship. The naive
pietistic emphasis on ‘personal relationship with Jesus’ is no doubt open to
various criticisms. It is important that ‘Jesus’ here should really be ‘Jesus
Christ of Nazareth’ (Acts 3.6), and not a fantasy figure whose pure
contemporaneity is detached from a fleshly, historical existence. It is
important that the relationship with Jesus should be located within a
trinitarian and communal framework. With these qualifications, however, talk of
a ‘personal relationship with Jesus’ comes much closer to the truth than a
supposedly more sophisticated description of Christian existence in primarily
sociological categories, which would in effect deny to the Christian community
its foundation and dwelling-place within the divine life. The life of the risen
Jesus is not the secret preserve of himself and his Father, as
6 Elizabeth Castelli argues that in Rom.
7.1 — 6 Paul 'uses a recognized hierarchical relationship to illuminate his
point about another hierarchical relationship ... By using women to think with,
Paul (like other authors who use gender and social roles as metaphors and
analogies) helps to underwrite the understanding of women’s roles on which his
argument depends’ ('Romans’, in E. Schussler Fiorenza (ed.), Searching the
Scriptures, vol. 11: A Feminist Commentary, New York: Crossroad,
1994; London, SCM Press, 1995, 272—300; 283). Castelli later makes a similar
point about the use of the image of slavery (e.g. in Rom. 6.22): 'While this
passage is clearly not about slavery (neither for it nor against it), it
depends on the reality of slavery to convey its meanings and therefore
reinscribes the relation of slavery’ (294). But when in 1 Cor. 7.23 Paul
writes, 'You were bought with a price; do not become slaves of humans’, the
image of the Christian as Christ’s slave (cf. v. 22b) sets the metaphorical
sense in opposition to the literal one; a similar disjunction also
underlies the qualified argument against marriage in 1 Cor. 7.32 —5 (cf. 6.13 —
17). A critique of 'metaphors of domination’ (295), even where the metaphorical
application is detached from the original social relation and is perhaps
critical of it, presupposes the possibility and desirability of a pure,
anarchic, utopian language — a language without arche, without
imperatives, and without opposites (feminist emphasis on multiplicity is
'inimical to’ that is, opposed to, 'binary opposition’ or 'dualism’
(286)). In substance, Castelli’s objection to the Pauline text is that it is
written not in the language of an imagined utopia but in koine Greek. though
the human Jesus had somehow ceased to represent humankind in his relationship
to the Father. It is a shared life that arises out of the promise, 'I am
with you always, to the close of the age' (Matt. 28.20).
As in marriage, the
relationship of Christ and the Christian is an affair of the body. It is
the death of 'the body of Christ' that makes it possible; and in his
resurrection Jesus resumes his body, rather than finally casting it off. The
attempt in 1 Corinthians 15 to articulate the difference between the present,
frail body of flesh and blood and the glorified body that Jesus already
possesses is so tortuous precisely because Paul will not concede that the word
'body' is more appropriately applied to empirical human reality than to
eschatological destiny. Without his body, the risen Christ would not still be
Jesus. But if there is no disembodied humanity in the case of Jesus Christ, the
same must be true of those who are in Christ. It is in their bodies that they
are one with him — in the concreteness, materiality and wholeness of their
existence.
As in marriage, the
existence of each of the partners is oriented towards the other rather
than centred in the self. Indeed, marriage gives only an inadequate picture of
this other-orientation. The terms 'husband' and 'wife' do not exhaustively
identify the man and woman who are united in marriage, for each of them is more
than the spouse of the other. In the case of Christ and the Christian, however,
that quali®cation does not apply. Jesus would not be Christ without his
relation to those who are 'in Christ'; he would not be himself. Similarly, the
term 'Christian' denotes not just the most important among a number of relationships
in which one is involved, but the relationship that comprehends all other
relationships — a relationship of absolute belonging. 'If we live, we live to
the Lord; if we die, we die to the Lord; and so, whether we live or whether we
die, we are the Lord's' (Rom. 14.8).
It follows that, as
in marriage, the relationship of Christ and the Christian is exclusive,
and indeed that this is a bodily exclusiveness. 'The body is not for porneia
but for the Lord, and the Lord is for the body' (1 Cor. 6.13). For a man and a
woman to join together in porneia, becoming 'one body' and 'one flesh',
would be to subvert the union with Christ, with whom one is ‘one spirit’
(6.16-17). It would be a sin against Christ and against one’s own body, which,
as the temple of the Holy Spirit, is Christ’s (6.18—19). Even marriage itself
may detract, in some respects, from the exclusiveness of the relationship with
the Lord (7.32—5). Marriage, however, is not a sin. On the contrary, ‘it was
ordained for a remedy against sin, and to avoid fornication’ — as the Book of
Common Prayer puts it, following 1 Corinthians 7.2. In marriage the body of
each partner is oriented towards the other (7.4), in a parable of the
relationship of Christ and the Christian that differs fundamentally from the
destructive caricature that occurs in porneia.
As in marriage, the
relationship of Christ and the Christian is intended to be fruitful.
Belonging to another has as its goal ‘that we might bear fruit for God’ (Rom.
7.4). Marriage ‘was ordained for the procreation of children, to be brought up
in the fear and nurture of the Lord, and to the praise of his holy Name’ (Book
of Common Prayer). This fruitfulness might be identihed with the ‘fruit of the
Spirit’, which is ‘love, joy, peace, patience, kindness, goodness, gentleness,
faithfulness, selfcontrol’; a life that is fruitful along these lines will
have no place for ‘the works of the flesh’ or for gratifying ‘the desire of the
flesh’ (Gal. 5.16—24). This true fruitfulness is independent of marriage, or of
fertility within marriage. It may well be that it is the single man or woman
who is most ‘anxious about the affairs of the Lord’ (1 Cor. 7.32, 34) and who
is therefore most ‘fruitful’. Where there is marriage and family life, however,
this will be one of the primary communal contexts in which love, joy, peace,
patience and kindness must come to fruition. It is in the midst of intimate
human relations of one kind or another that the testing implied in the
statement, ‘You shall know them by their fruits’ (Matt. 7.16) is carried out.
The source of this fruitfulness is Christ himself, through the Spirit: ‘It is
the one who abides in me, and I in him, who bears much fruit; for apart from me
you can do nothing’ (Jn. 15.5).
For
when we were in the flesh, the passions of sins were through the law at work in
our members, to bearfruit for death. (v. 5) The present state, in
which there is fruit-bearing for God (v. 4), is now contrasted with a past
state in which there was fruit-bearing for death ± the death that is disclosed
but also overcome in Christ's death and our participation in it. The vocabulary
± flesh, sin, members, fruit, death ± continues to echo chapter 6; what is new
in chapter 7 is the emphasis on ‘law’. In chapter 6 it was said that ‘sin will
not rule over you, for you are not under law but under grace’ (v. 14, cf. v.
15), yet the implied claim that the law furthers the dominion of sin was not
clarified ± despite the obvious objection that the law actually hinders and
limits sin’s dominion, rather than furthering it. The role of the law within
the drama of sin and salvation is the theme of chapter 7, although it is
introduced only indirectly in the opening verses. The chapter is addressed ‘to
those who know the law’, and it opens with an assertion about the law: that it
rules over a man only during his lifetime (v. 1). In the example of the married
woman whose husband dies, the emphasis lies on her change of status in relation
to the law: once bound by ‘the law of the husband’, she is now free from this law
(vv. 2, 3). The ‘dying to sin’ that is the theme of 6.1 — 11 becomes in 7.4 a
‘dying to the law’. As in 6.14, the law is apparently assigned a negative role,
but as yet without explanation. In the law±grace contrast and in the image of
the married woman, ‘law’ and ‘Christ’ are related antithetically to one another
± even though the rest of chapter 7 will emphasize that ‘law’ remains ‘the law
of God’, the same God as the God and Father of our Lord Jesus Christ. Paul does
not intend to be a Marcionite ± although it is his law±grace antithesis that
enables Marcion to understand himself as a Paulinist.
If
Paul’s aim is merely to legitimate the non-practice of Judaism in the Gentile
communities that he has founded, the antithesis is not the best or most obvious
way of achieving this. Although there are antithetical elements in Galatians
(for example, in the contrast between the curse of the law and the blessing of
Abraham (3.8—14)), the dominant model presents the law as a preliminary stage
in the divine ‘education of the human race’. The law was our paidagogos
— our ‘schoolmaster’, in the Authorized Version’s free but vivid rendering —
whose task was to discipline our childish follies and prepare us for the adult
life which is now ours through Christ (3.21-4.11). We are free from the law in
the same way as we are free from the preliminary disciplines of childhood.
Although in the Pauline version of this theme the law is only indirectly of
divine origin (3.19, 4.1-3, 8-9), this ‘educational’ model later made it possible
for Irenaeus to emphasize the coherence of the unfolding divine dealings with
humankind, in opposition both to Marcionite antithesis and, indirectly, to
Judaism.7 Yet in Romans, supposedly a more considered and
mature text than Galatians, there is no trace of the ‘educational’ model, and
antithesis predominates.8 Having established the antithesis in Romans 6.14
and 7.1-4, Paul begins in 7.5 to explain why it is necessary. The law is
associated with the rule of sin because our sinful passions were at work in us through
the law. It is not said that the law simply proved powerless to restrain
our sinful passions, like a schoolmaster unable to control an unruly class. It
is said that the law actively provoked and incited the sinful passions that
rule over the flesh. The law is part of the problem. Yet, as Paul will
immediately emphasize, it remains the law of God and its requirements are holy,
just and good. The problem must lie not in the law as such but in its human
addressees.
Two narratives help
to shed light on these cryptic Pauline statements. One is the story of Israel’s
experiences in the
7 Direct use of relevant texts from
Galatians is found in Irenaeus, Adversus haereses, iv. 2.7 (Gal. 3.24,
the Pauline image of the law as paidagogos) and iii.16.7 (Gal. 4.4, the
sending of the Son 'in the fullness of time’).
8 In developmental accounts of Pauline
theology, Paul is said to have reached a 'balanced’ view of the law in Romans
that contrasts with and corrects the extremism of the earlier Galatian letter. 'Whereas
in Galatians Paul sees scarcely any value at all in the Old Testament Law,
which did not even have God as its author (Gal. 3.19), in Romans, ''the law is
holy and the commandment is holy and just and good’’ (7.12)’ (J. W. Drane, Paul:
Libertine or Legalist? A Study in the Theology of the Major Pauline Epistles, London:
SPCK, 1975, 73). H. Hubner too argues that Paul in Romans modifies the negative
verdict on the law he had pronounced in Galatians, suggesting that 'it was
perhaps the very fact of Galatians becoming known in Jerusalem that occasioned
the posing of critical questions to the author - which the latter then also,
contrary to all expectations, began to ask himself . . . [T]he difference
between Galatians and Romans is best explained if we assume that there was a
far from trivial theological development on the part of Paul between the two
letters’ (Law in Paul's Thought, ET Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1984,
55). Developmental accounts will tend to overlook both the independent
significance of Galatians, which is reduced to a moment in a process of
development, and the presence in Romans of elements that are more radical than
anything in Galatians.
wilderness;
this will be treated in connection with verses 8-10. The other is Augustine’s
well-known account of an act of youthful folly, in which an act of theft was
provoked not by the desirability of the object but simply by the law’s
prohibition.9 Augustine writes:
I
wanted to steal, and steal I did, although I was not compelled by any lack —
unless it were the lack of a sense of justice, or a distaste for what was right
and a love of wickedness. For of what I stole I already had plenty, and much
better at that, and I had no wish to enjoy the things I sought to steal, but
only to enjoy the theft itself and the sin. There was a pear-tree near our
vineyard, laden with fruit that was tempting neither for its colour nor for its
flavour. To shake the fruit off the tree and carry off the pears, I and a gang
of dissolute boys set off late at night — for we had continued our games in the
streets till then, as was our disreputable habit — and removed an enormous
quantity, not to eat them ourselves but simply to throw to the pigs. Perhaps we
ate some of them, but our pleasure consisted in doing what was forbidden. (Confessions,
ii.4.9)
This
apparently trivial incident is signihcant because it enables Augustine to
identify and isolate an element in the act of sin that is normally concealed.
On one dehnition, sin is the choice of a lesser good in preference to a higher
one. All the good gifts of creation ‘can be occasions of sin because, good
though they are, they are of the lowest order of good, and if we are too much
tempted by them we abandon those higher and better things: you yourself, O Lord
our God, your truth and your law’ (ii.5.10). This account of the nature of sin
recalls the analysis of the confusion of the creature with the creator in
Wisdom of Solomon 13, echoed by Paul in Romans 1. The good gifts of creation
serve only to conceal the creator: humans ‘were unable from the good things
that are seen to know the one who is, nor did they recognize the maker while
attending to his works ... If through delight in the beauty of these things
they assumed them to be gods, let them know how much better than these is their
9 The Augustine passage is cited by C.
H. Dodd, in connection with Rom. 7.7—8: Augustine, 'a master of introspective
psychology, as well as the greatest interpreter of Paul’, articulates here what
is actually 'quite a common experience’ (The Epistle of Paul to the Romans
[1932], London: Collins, 1959, 127). Here, Augustine interprets Paul as
he engages in 'introspective psychology’; Augustine’s narrative tacitly
presupposes the Pauline passage.
Lord,
for the author of beauty created them’ (Wis. 13.1, 3). According to Augustine,
this substitution of a lesser, created good for the higher, uncreated good is
characteristic of sin in general; sin is, as it were, parasitic on the goodness
of creation. The problem is that this does not explain why he stole the pears.
It is true that even these poor-quality pears were God’s creatures and
therefore ‘good’. But that was not why he stole them. He did not want the
pears, he wanted only to steal; there was no trace even of a distorted beauty
or goodness in that act. An alternative dehnition of sin is therefore needed.
Sin, we might say, is that human pride which pursues what belongs to God alone:
All
who desert you and exalt themselves against you are perversely imitating you .
. . What was it then that pleased me in that act of theft? And in what did I
corruptly and perversely imitate my Lord? Did I wish to act contrary to your
law by deceit because I had not the power to do so by force? Did I, like a
prisoner with restricted liberty, do with impunity what is not permitted so as
to acquire a faint resemblance of your omnipotence? (Confessions,
ii.6.14)
It was
the divine prohibition of theft that incited the sixteen- year-old Augustine to
steal the pears. In Pauline language, his ‘sinful passions’ were at work in him
‘through the law’. Human pride, aspiring to omnipotence, cannot endure the
restriction of its freedom that the law represents; and so the law unwittingly
provokes the very actions that it prohibits. It proves to be counterproductive.
Transgression is a
dehant claim to freedom. In the act of transgression it is therefore
transgression itself that is loved, as well as or even in place of the
forbidden object. The theft of the pears is a ‘pure’ example of this love of
transgression for its own sake, independent of its object, and it suggests that
this same assertion of freedom may still be found in those transgressive acts
where, unlike the pears, the object is desired. The story of the theft
of the pears occurs in the context of an account of the adolescent Augustine’s
hrst sexual experiences. At this time it was his mother who represented for him
the voice of the divine law. ‘Whose words were they but yours which you were
chanting in my ears through your mother, your faithful servant? . . .
Her concern (and in the secret of my conscience I recall the memory of her
admonition, delivered with vehement anxiety) was that I should not fall into
fornication, and above all that I should not commit adultery with someone
else's wife' (ii.3.7). But the young Augustine is influenced more by a peer
group in which ‘the greater the sin the more they gloried in it — so that I
took pleasure in the same vices not only for the pleasure's sake but also for
the praise' (ii.3.7). In the case of the theft, it is only the presence of others
that makes the sinful action pleasurable: ‘Had I been alone, it would have
given me absolutely no pleasure, nor would I have committed it' (ii.9.17). The
object of the theft gives none of the pleasure that is found in sexual objects,
but in both cases there is the pleasure of transgression itself, in which one's
knowledge of oneself as a transgressor is confirmed by the admiration of one's
peers.
Augustine's
searching analysis of his adolescent follies recalls the Pauline description of
those who, ‘knowing the decree of God that those who practise such things are
worthy of death, not only do them but also approve those who practise them'
(Rom. 1.32). In itself, to do what is forbidden means only that the prohibition
is ignored (as in the case of Monica's warning to the young Augustine); the law
proves powerless to secure the obedience it seeks. But where transgression is
not only practised but also approved in principle, transgression itself belongs
to the object of the act. For those who are ‘in the flesh' (7.5), the decree of
God is a provocation that incites resistance in both deed and word. ‘The mind
of the flesh is hostile to God' (8.7): it does not and cannot submit to the law
of God, but finds occasion in the law of God to express its hostility to God.
Thus (according to Augustine's reading of the Pauline text) our ‘sinful
passions' are at work in us ‘through the law'. Adolescent rebellion becomes a
parable of human alienation from God. Using an image that recurs in Freud,[xlv] Augustine later argues that the law, however good
in itself, only augments the evil desire by forbidding it - just as the rush of
water which flows incessantly in a particular direction becomes more violent
when it meets with any impediment, and when it has overcome the obstacle falls
in greater volume, and with increased impetuosity rushes on in its downward
course. In some strange way the very object which we covet becomes all the more
desirable when it is forbidden [quod concupisciturfit iocondius dum vetatur].
And this is the sin which by the commandment deceives and by it kills, whenever
transgression is actually added, which does not occur where there is no law.
(De spir. et litt., 6)
Apart
from the law, concupiscence would simply be a morally neutral natural force. It
is ‘through the law’ that it is present in us in the form of ‘sinful passions’
for which transgression is not only a means to an end but also an end in
itself.
But
now we are freed from the law, having died to that which held us bound, so that
we may serve in newness of the Spirit and not in oldness of the letter. (v. 6) ‘The letter’
draws attention to the fact that the law is a written text (cf. 2 Cor. 3.6).
The writing is that of Moses, but at its heart is the divine writing of the
Decalogue, ‘written’ [eggegramment] or ‘engraved’ [entetupomene]
in tablets of stone by the finger of God. As Moses himself says of the
Decalogue: ‘These words the Lord spoke to all your assembly at the mountain out
of the midst of the fire, the cloud and the thick darkness, with a loud voice,
and he added no more. And he wrote them upon two tables of stone and gave them
to me’ (Deut. 5.22).[xlvi] To hear the divine voice was Israel’s unique
privilege: ‘Did any people ever hear the voice of God speaking out of the midst
of the fire, as you have heard, and still live?’ (4.33). For Paul, however,
this is an event of worldwide significance. The coming of the law was an event
no less universal in its scope than Adam’s sin (Rom. 5.12-14, 20—1); the
Gentile Christians addressed in Romans 7 are therefore ‘not under law . . . ’
(6.14) in the sense that they are no longer under law. No less than
Jews, they ‘know the law’ (7.1). Even in their pre-Christian days, they ‘knew
the decree of God . . . ’ (1.32): for ‘from early generations Moses has had in
every city those who preach him, for he is read every sabbath in the
synagogues’ (Acts 15.21). Those who were beyond the range of this preaching
still had ‘nature’ to instruct them in the law of God (Rom. 2.14—15). Israel
under the law of God discloses the situation of the entire world.
As Augustine rightly
argued, the antithesis between ‘letter’ and ‘Spirit’ does not involve a
contrast between the particularity of the one and the universality of the
other:
Now
carefully consider this entire passage, and see whether it says anything about
circumcision or the sabbath or anything else relating to a foreshadowing
sacrament. Does not its whole scope amount to this, that the letter which
forbids sin fails to give humans life, but rather ‘kills’ by increasing concupiscence
and by aggravating sinfulness by transgression — unless indeed grace liberates
us by the law of faith, which is in Christ Jesus, when his love is shed abroad
in our hearts by the Holy Spirit who is given to us? The apostle, having used
these words: ‘That we should serve in newness of the Spirit and not in oldness
of the letter’, goes on to inquire: ‘What shall we say then? Is the law sin?
God forbid! But I would not have known sin except by the law; I would not have
known lust [concupiscentiam nesciebam] if the law had not said, Thou
shalt not lust [non concupisces]. But sin, taking occasion by the
commandment, wrought in me all manner of concupiscence . . . ’ (De spir. et
litt., 25)
The
point here is that the law’s prohibition of concupiscence (Rom. 7.7—8) is as
universal in scope as the concupiscence that it unwittingly serves to generate.
As Augustine points out, the same is true of the commandments, Thou shalt not
commit adultery, Thou shalt not kill, Thou shalt not steal, summarized in the commandment
to love our neighbour as ourself (13.8—9). ‘Love is the fulilling of the law’
(13.10), and this love — the caritas Dei — is ‘shed abroad in our hearts
[diffunditur in cordibus nostris] by the Holy Spirit who was given to
us’ (5.5). ‘There it was on tablets of stone that the hnger of God operated;
here it was on human hearts’ (De spir. et litt., 29). At Sinai there was
fear, at Pentecost, freedom: ‘The people on the earlier occasion were deterred
by a terrible fear from approaching the place where the law was given, whereas
in the other case the Holy Spirit came upon those who were gathered together in
expectation of his promised gift’ (29).
Paul’s
language about a service of God ‘in newness of the Spirit and not in oldness of
the letter’ says nothing about the content of that service. Yet the idea that
‘the letter’ requires one set of actions and ‘the Spirit’ another is alien to
this context, in which it is the universal heart of the law that is at issue
rather than the distinctive practices of Judaism — although it is within
Judaism that this universal heart of the law is disclosed. Since Paul himself
will later cite commandments from the Decalogue as still binding on Christians,
and then reduce them to love of neighbour (Rom. 13.8—10), it seems that
Augustine’s reading is correct: the letter—Spirit antithesis assumes a single content
to the divine will for humankind and contrasts instead the manner in
which this single content is promulgated. The law and its content remain ‘holy
and just and good’ (7.12) for Christians, but the question is how its
commandments can be ful®lled if their immediate result is simply to arouse ta
pathemata ton hamartion and evoke resistance (7.5). The answer — Paul’s and
Augustine’s answer — is that human ful®lment of the divine will can occur only
through the Spirit (7.6, cf. 8.4), in whom ‘the love of God’ that is the
fulhlment of the law is ‘shed abroad in our hearts’ (5.5). ‘The fruit of the
Spirit is love, joy, peace’, and so on, and ‘against such things there is no law’
(Gal. 5.22—3): for the love of neighbour that is the fruit of the Spirit is
also the fulhlment of ‘the whole law’ (5.14). Freedom from the law is freedom for
the ful®lment of the law through the Spirit, and so freedom from the law
in its absolute, abstract form as a demand that merely discloses sin and evokes
resistance.
In this
freedom, the law that is ‘holy and just and good’ and that discloses the divine
will for humankind is itself freed from human arbitrariness and taken up into a
new, comprehensive,
trinitarian
context. The ‘newness of the Spirit’ in which we now serve (Rom. 7.6) can also
be described as our belonging ‘to the one who has been raised from the dead, so
that we may bear fruit for God’ (7.4). In this new context, the law - which in
itself is ‘weak through the flesh’ (8.3) - becomes the law of freedom, ‘the law
of the Spirit of life in Christ Jesus’ (8.2); the fulfilment in us of the law’s
decree occurs through the Spirit and on the basis of God’s sending his only Son
in the likeness of sinful flesh (8.3—4). Such language indicates that the
Spirit is not an independent agent but ‘the Holy Spirit of the Father and the
Son’ (De spir. et litt., 59). ‘The Holy Spirit, according to the holy
scriptures, is neither of the Father alone, nor of the Son alone, but of both;
and so discloses to us the mutual love [caritatem communem] with which
the Father and the Son love one another’ (De trinitate, xv. 27). Indeed,
the Holy Spirit is that love: ‘The Holy Spirit, of whom [God] has given
us, causes us to abide in God and him in us; and this it is that love does’
(xv. 31). If the Holy Spirit is the mutual love of Father and Son, then we are
comprehended within that love when the love of God is shed abroad in our hearts
through the Holy Spirit (xv.31).
This trinitarian
context of the ‘newness of the Spirit’ which has replaced the ‘oldness of the
letter’ must be understood christologically, that is, in terms of the human
life of Jesus: for the law is ful®lled in us through the Spirit only insofar as
it is first fulfilled in him. It is true that the ‘obedience’ of Jesus is an
‘obedience unto death, even the death of the cross’ (Phil. 2.8) — an obedience
to a specific, unique divine vocation. But in his obedience to this vocation
Jesus also loves his neighbour and so fulfils the law: it was ‘for our sake’ [di'
humas] that ‘though he was rich he became poor’ (2 Cor. 8.9). If, although
he was ‘born under the law’ (Gal. 4.4), he ‘knew no sin’ (2 Cor. 5.21), then
his sinlessness consists in his fulfilment of the law. Although Paul does not
explicitly make this point, we may say that it is through the Spirit that the
human Jesus ful®ls the law and loves his neighbour. According to Augustine, the
creative role of the Holy Spirit in Jesus’ conception
is
intended as a manifestation of the grace of God. For it was by this grace that
a human, without any prior merit, was at the very beginning of his existence as
human so united in one person with the Word of God that the very person who was
Son of man was at the same time Son of God, and the very person who was Son of
God was at the same time Son of man. In the adoption of his human nature into
the divine, grace itself became in a way so natural to the man as to leave no
room for the entrance of sin. It is this grace that is signi®ed by the Holy
Spirit; for he, though in his own nature God, may also be called the gift of
God. (Enchiridion, 40)
Human
freedom to fulfil the law and to love one's neighbour is, in the first
instance, Jesus' freedom. This freedom of divine grace comes naturally
to Jesus because grace is the origin of his being — the grace of the Spirit
which in him unites a human nature that is in itself unworthy of grace with the
divine nature, as the Son of man is identified with the Son of God. The mutual
love of the Father and the Son, which is the Spirit, is thus identified with
the mutual love of the Father and the human Jesus. Through the Spirit, the
intradivine love is extended into the human realm and assumes the new form of a
divine—human relationship of mutual love. In and through this
relationship, the telos of human existence — which is to answer the
prior divine love with love of God and of neighbour — is ful®lled. To be ‘in
Christ Jesus' is to participate, through the Spirit, in that telos.
This
attempt to reconstruct a trinitarian and christological logic from the Pauline
reference to the ‘newness of the Spirit' set out from the fact that the new
state that is ascribed to the Spirit in Romans 7.6 is also ascribed to the
crucified and risen Christ and, indirectly, to God in verse 4. Through the
action of the triune God, a new mode of human existence has been brought into
being whose ‘newness' is that of a ‘new creation' (2 Cor. 5.17, Gal. 6.15).
Reconstructing the logic of this divine action requires one to fill out the
fragmentary although still coherent Pauline account with material from
elsewhere — especially from the synoptic emphasis on the role of the Spirit in
the life of Jesus. To an exegesis concerned only with the surface of texts,
this may seem a questionable procedure. But a theological exegesis, concerned
with the texts in their relation to their subject matter, must on occasion
pursue their logic beyond what they explicitly say. ‘The language of the Word
of God, in order to exercise us, has caused those things to be sought into with
the greater zeal which do not lie on the surface [in promptu] but are to
be found only in the hidden depths [in abdito], and drawn out from
there’ (De trin., xv.27).
A new mode of human
existence, a new creation originating in the being-in-action of the triune God:
this is the only possible framework for Christian ethics, and, more
specihcally, for our particular theme, a Christian understanding of sexuality.
In retracing the Pauline argument up to this point, nothing has been said that
is not directly and immediately relevant to that theme. It is this account of
the divine being-in-action that is the context of Paul’s reflection on the
anomalies of ‘desire’ — concupiscence, libido — in the verses that follow.
DESIRE in THE DESERT [VERSES 7-9)
What
then shall we say? Is the law sin? Certainly not! But I would not have known
sin except through the law. I would not have known desire if the law had not
said, You shall not desire.
(v. 7) With the death of her husband, the married woman is freed from the law;
and we too have died to the law and are freed from it, so as to belong to
Christ within the new life of the Spirit, bearing fruit for God. The new life
contrasts with the old, in which ‘the passions of sins’ were at work within our
bodies ‘through the law’. The intimate relation of sin and law means that
freedom from sin (Rom. 6) must also be freedom from the law (7.1—6). ‘Sin will
no longer rule over you’, when ‘you are not under law’ (6.14). If sin and law
are so intimately related, are they to be identified? Does the law provoke sin
in the sense that the actions and abstentions it enjoins are actually sinful?
The suggestion is absurd, but it does enable Paul to show how it is that the
law can be both the holy, just and good law of God and incapable of securing
for humans the ‘life’ that it intends. In the background here is the question
why, contrary to all the expectations of Paul the Pharisee and persecutor of
the church, the glory of the law has now been eclipsed by the surpassing glory
of Christ (2 Cor. 3.10).
The law is not sin,
but it provokes sin. The ‘knowledge of sin’ that it gives is a hrst-hand
knowledge. Without the law I would not have known the sin of ‘desire’; through
the law sin worked in me ‘every kind of desire’: what would not have been known
without the law is this activity of sin. A law that merely disclosed sin
by dehning it would not be a problem but would be positively benehcial; a law
that in dehning sin actually provokes it is another matter. The particular sin
that it provokes is ‘desire’ (epithumia) - the desire prohibited by the
tenth commandment. In the Masoretic form of Exodus 20.17, what is prohibited
is desire for one’s neighbour’s property, of which a number of examples are
given:
You
shall not desire your neighbour’s house. You shall not desire your neighbour’s
wife, his male or his female servant, his ox, his ass, or anything that belongs
to your neighbour.
Here,
the repetition of ‘you shall not desire’ appears to be redundant. In the parallel
passage in Deut. 5.21, the order is different:
You
shall not desire your neighbour’s wife. And you shall not desire your
neighbour’s house, his held, his male or female servant, his ox, his ass, or
anything that belongs to your neighbour.
In the Exodus
version of the tenth commandment, the emphasis is on property, and the sexual
element, present in the reference to the neighbour’s wife and his female slave,
is not emphasized. In the Deuteronomy version, the reversal of ‘house’ and
‘wife’ has the effect of making the sexual element much more prominent. It is
because there is no difference in principle between desiring one’s neighbour’s
house and desiring his ox that the second ‘you shall not desire’ is redundant
in Exodus 20.17. But desiring one’s neighbour’s wife is quite different to
desiring his house or his ox, and the effect here of the repeated ‘you shall
not desire’ is to differentiate the desire for adultery from other kinds of
desire for one’s neighbour’s property, thus linking the tenth commandment to
the seventh as well as the eighth. As the most powerful and dangerous of all
desires, sexual desire for a prohibited object is distinguished from other
desires. Desire for prohibited objects may take various forms, but the sexual
form is the hrst and most obvious of these, a paradigm for the others.
In the Septuagint
version quoted by Paul in Romans 7.7, Exodus 20.17 is identical in wording to
Deuteronomy 5.21. In both cases, the tenth commandment opens by prohibiting the
desire for adultery (ouk epithumeseis ten gunaika tou plesion sou), and
continues with a separate prohibition of desire for the neighbour’s house,
held, and so on, again introduced by ‘you shall not desire’ (ouk epithumeseis).12 The result is that sexual
desire is presented as paradigmatic of all desires for prohibited objects. Thus
in Paul too ‘desire’ (epithumia) is not exclusively sexual, but it is
primarily and paradigmatically sexual. Desire is associated with flesh.
We are to ‘put on the Lord Jesus Christ and make no provision for the desires [eis
epithumias] of the hesh’ (Rom. 13.14). Of the six prohibited practices
named in the previous verse, two - koitai, ‘beds’, a euphemism for
sexual intercourse, and aselgeiai, ‘debauchery’ or ‘licentiousness’ -
are explicitly sexual, and the other four (‘revelry’, ‘drunkenness’,
‘quarrelling’ and ‘jealousy’) appear to relate not to discrete ‘desires of the
hesh’ but to the type of social context within which illicit sexual activity
takes place. ‘The desires of the hesh’ do not consist in a series of separate
orientations, one relating to sex, another to alcohol, and so on, but to a
complex of interrelated and inseparable drives which express themselves in the
type of situation to which the list of prohibited practices refers. Similarly,
in Galatians 5.16-17 it is said that those who walk by the Spirit ‘will not
fulhl the desire of the hesh [epithumian sarkos]’, and that ‘the hesh
desires [epithumei] against the Spirit, and the Spirit against the
hesh’; in Galatians 5.24 it is said that those who belong to Christ ‘have
crucihed the hesh with its passions and desires [sun tais pathemasin kai
tais epithumiais]’. Once again, sexual desire is
12 The
significance for Paul’s argument of the Septuagintal form of the tenth
commandment is noted by Daniel Boyarin, in his A Radical Jew: Paul and the
Politics of Identity, Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of
California Press, 163. According to Boyarin, the law 'directly and necessarily
stirs the passions’ in the sense that, in Gen. 1.28, it 'enjoins the
procreation of children’ (169). The problem for this interpretation is that the
specific commandment which 'worked in me every kind of desire’ (7.8) is not 'Be
fruitful and multiply’ but 'You shall not desire’ (7.7). Reading the tenth
commandment back into Gen. 2 -3 is possible, but does not resolve this problem.
paradigmatic
here of desire in general: for ‘the works of the flesh’ are, first,
‘fornication, uncleanness, debauchery [porneia, akatharsia, aselgeia],
although they also take non-sexual forms in ‘idolatry, magic, enmity,
quarrelling, jealousy, anger’ and so on (Gal. 5.19—21). Like the English
‘lust’, epithumia can on occasion stand for sexual desire without the
need to specify its object. The Thessalonians are warned to abstain from porneia,
to keep their body (to heautou skeuos) in holiness and honour and not to
act ‘in the passion of desire [me en pathei epithumias] like the
Gentiles who do not know God’ (1 Thes. 4.3—5). In this context, epithumia
is closely related to the first part of the tenth commandment, ‘You shall not
desire [ouk epithumeseis] your neighbour’s wife’; for in the following
verse Paul warns his readers not to ‘transgress and cheat one’s brother in this
matter’ (v. 6), with obvious reference to adultery.13
The desire
that the tenth commandment prohibits is primarily but not exclusively sexual,
and the prohibition even of the desire for prohibited objects sets this
commandment apart from the others by tracing the actions prohibited by the
other negative commandments back to the motivation in which they originate. The
tenth commandment is for Paul not just one commandment among many; like the
commandment to love one's neighbour, it is a summary of the entire law. The
whole law is ful®lled in the single statement: you shall not desire . . . In
tracing all sin back to desire, Paul is at one with James: ‘Desire
13 That
the tenth commandment is concerned primarily but not exclusively with sexual
desire is also acknowledged by the author of 4 Maccabees, for whom the commandment,
'You shall not desire your neighbour’s wife or anything else that is your
neighbour’s’ means that 'not only is reason proved to rule over the frenzied
urge of sexual desire [tes hedupatheias], but also over every desire [pases
epithumias]' (4 Macc. 2.5). 'Not only’ refers back to the example ofJoseph
that has just been cited. There is also evidence in this Hellenistic Jewish
text of a negative view of epithumia itself, irrespective of its object.
'Self-control [sophrosune] is dominance over the desires [epikrateia
ton epithumion]’ (1.31). David on one occasion 'opposed reason to desire [te
epithumia ton logismon]’ (3.16); for desire is in itself irrational (alogistos
epithumia, 3.11). Thus, as in Rom. 7.7, the tenth commandment can be seen
as prohibiting desire itself: the law told us 'not to desire [mee epithumein]’
(4 Macc. 2.6). This negative sense is also present in Philo, according to whom
'the last commandment opposes desire, for he [Moses] knew desire [ten
epithumian] to be resourceful and insidious. For all the passions of the
soul which stir and shake it against its proper nature [para phusin] and
do not let it continue in sound health are hard to deal with, but desire is
hardest of all’ (de decalogo, 142).
[epithumia] when it has
conceived gives birth to sin; and sin when it is full-grown brings forth death'
(Jas. 1.15). If agape is the positive content of the law, as ‘you shall
love [agapeseis] your neighbour as yourself' suggests (Gal. 5.14, Rom.
13.9-10), then its negative content is summarized in the prohibition even of
the desire for prohibited objects. Positive and negative belong together:
loving one's neighbour as oneself is incompatible with desire for his wife, or
rather, with desire for the neighbour who is herself the wife of another. For
the sake of agape, eros must be subjected to severe restrictions, so as
to eliminate not just the erotic act but even the desire for it. Jesus' saying
makes the same point: ‘I say to you that everyone who looks at a woman to
desire her [pros to epithumesai auten] has already committed adultery
with her in his heart [en te kardia autou]' (Matt. 5.28). This drastic
restriction of ‘normal' male sexual conduct is a negative consequence of the
‘great commandment', which enjoins the love of God, and its corollary, the love
of neighbour (Matt. 22.36-40). We do not ‘love the Lord our God with all our
heart [kardia] . . .' when that ‘heart' is hlled with the fantasy of
sexual intercourse with the object of the erotic gaze. We do not ‘love our
neighbour as ourselves' when we make her (or him) the object of that fantasy.
The prohibition of the desire and the fantasy is intended to create space for agapoe.
For Augustine too,
the tenth commandment is a summary of the entire law. The apostle ‘purposely
selected this general precept, in which he included everything, as if this were
the voice of the law prohibiting us from all sin, when he says, “Thou shalt not
covet'' [non concupisces] ; for there is no sin committed except by evil
concupiscence [concupiscentia]' (De spir. et litt., 6). Here,
‘concupiscence' does not refer exclusively to sexual desire. But because desire
for prohibited sexual objects is the paradigmatic form of the tenth
commandment, Augustine elsewhere identihes concupiscence specihcally with
sexual desire. When Paul confesses that ‘I do not do what I want, but I do the
very thing that I hate' (Rom. 7.15), it is the specihcally sexual instance of
concupiscence that he has in mind (De nuptiis et concupiscentia, i.30).
‘The law too wills not that which I also will not; for it wills not that I
should have concupiscence, for it says: “Thou shalt not lust”; and I am no less
unwilling to cherish so evil a desire’ (i.30). The Pauline abbreviation of the
tenth commandment enables Augustine to argue that concupiscence or ‘lust’ is
itself sin, shifting the emphasis from desire for the illicit sexual object to
the desire itself. Concupiscence does not belong to the original constitution
of marriage; it derives from the Fall, where Adam and Eve’s shame at their nakedness
is symptomatic of their enslavement to a new power that has subjected the body
to the primacy of genital union. The convention that nakedness, especially of
the genitals, should be covered is an attempt to resist the imperative of
concupiscence; and this is reinforced by the law’s prohibition. Romans 7.7-25
is read as commentary on Genesis 3.
The claim that
concupiscence does not belong to the original constitution of marriage will be
greeted with incredulity by Pelagian or semi-Pelagian readers; but Augustine
insists that the phenomenon of shame marks a fundamental reordering and
distortion of the sexuality that belongs to the creation of humans as male and
female. Challenged by his Pelagian opponent to show how there can be bodily
marriage without sexual connection, Augustine replies:
I
do not show him any bodily marriage without sexual connection; but then,
neither does he show me any case of sexual connection which is without shame.
In paradise, however, if sin had not preceded, there would indeed have been no
procreation without sexual union, but this union would have been without shame;
for in the sexual union there would have been a quiet acquiescence of the
members, not a lust of the flesh [concupiscentia carnis] resulting in
shame. (De nupt. et conc., ii.37)
Marriage
was instituted, hrst, for the procreation of children in accordance with the
divine command, ‘Be fruitful and multiply’ (Gen. 1.29). ‘For accomplishing this
good work, various members were created, suited to each sex; these members were
of course in existence before sin, but they were not objects of shame’ (De nupt.
et conc., i.23). Marriage was instituted, second, for the maintenance of
hdelity and chastity, and third, for the creation of a sacramental bond. It is
said of marriage as originally created: ‘A man shall leave his father and his
mother, and shall cleave to his wife, and the two shall become one flesh’ (Gen.
2.24): ‘This the apostle applies to the case of Christ and the Church, and
calls it then a “great sacrament’’ [sacramentum magnum, Eph. 5.32]. What
then in Christ and the Church is “great” is in the case of each married couple
very small, but even then it is the sacrament of an inseparable union’ (v. 32).
Marriage is good, but concupiscence is evil - for the law tells us, ‘Thou shalt
not lust’ (non concupisces). If sexual union was originally accompanied
by desire for pleasure, this was a desire subject to the will which ‘would
arise at the summons of will just at the time when chaste prudence would have
perceived beforehand that intercourse was necessary’, quite different to the
disorderly, immoderate concupiscence to which we are now subject and which
causes us shame (Contra duas epistolas Pelagia- norum, i.34).
Concupiscence as we
now know it is inseparable from shame. If this concupiscentia carnis be
asked
how
it is that acts now bring shame which once were free from shame, will not her
answer be that she only took up residence in the human body after sin? And,
therefore, that the apostle described her influence as the ‘law of sin’, since
she subjected humans to herself when they were unwilling to remain subject to
their God; and that it was she who made the first married pair ashamed at that
moment when they covered their loins; just as everyone is still ashamed, and seeks
privacy for the sexual act, not daring even to allow children, whom they have
begotten in just this manner, to witness what they do. It was against this
modesty of natural shame that the Cynic philosophers, in the error of their
astonishing shamelessness, struggled so hard: they thought that the intercourse
of husband and wife, since it was lawful and honourable, should therefore be
performed in public. Such barefaced obscenity deserved to receive the name of
dogs; and so they went by the title of ‘Cynics’. (De nupt. et conc.,
i.24)
The
concealment of sexual intercourse even within marriage is a sign of the shame
that is integral to concupiscence. In one sense, the Cynics were right to think
that the association between sexual union and shame is unnatural, the product
of secondary conventions that are at odds with the law of nature; they were
right to imagine an original, shame-free sexuality. They went wrong in failing
to see the irreversible necessity of the secondary conventions in a distorted,
corrupted state in which the original state remains inaccessible. Believing the
conventions to be merely arbitrary and reformable, they did not notice that the
way back to paradise was barred by the cherubim and the flaming sword.
Concupiscence
is thus an anonymous, impersonal power that permeates human life and penetrates
into the heart even of marriage. As Paul argues, husbands and wives are not to
deprive one another of sexual union — ‘lest Satan tempt you through lack of
self-control [dia ten akrasian humonf (i Cor. 7.5). This is precisely
the temptation which, in a fallen world, constitutes a further reason for
marriage: ‘Because of the temptation to immorality [dia de tas porneias]
each man should have his own wife and each woman her own husband’ (7.2). Quite
apart from the question of procreation, sexual intercourse within marriage is
pragmatically necessary — although this necessity is more that of a
‘permission’ than of a ‘command’ (7.6) — since its purpose is to contain
the concupiscence of both man and woman, which might otherwise express itself
in acts of porneia. ‘To escape this evil, even those embraces of husband
and wife that do not have procreation as their object, but serve an overbearing
concupiscence, are permitted, so far as to be within range of forgiveness,
though not prescribed by way of commandment . . . Now in a case where
permission [venia] must be given, it certainly cannot be argued that
there is not some amount of sin’ (De nupt. et conc., i.i6). Augustine’s
intention here is to underline the continuity between the concupiscence which
finds expression in acts of porneia and that which occurs in marriage.
If marital intercourse is in part a substitute for porneia, and if, in
its absence, porneia may in turn be a substitute for marital intercourse,
then something of the character of porneia must be present even within
marital intercourse. The happily married couple, whose sexual fidelity to one
another is never seriously tested, is perhaps not in a position to cast the
first stone at the less fortunate. Yet marriage is indeed the divinely ordained
context in which the evil of concupiscence is restrained and indeed put to good
use.
According
to Augustine, it is permissible to seek the pleasure of sexual union rather
than procreation so long as there is no attempt actually to prevent conception.
This qualihcation is not directed against the modern concept of 'family
planning'. Augustine's criticism is directed against those (he assumes them to
be legally married) who detach the divine permission from the divine command by
practising sexual intercourse in the context of a settled intention not to have
children. This intention is expressed in a variety of practices, contraceptive
and otherwise:
Having
proceeded thus far, they are betrayed into exposing their children, which were
born against their will. They hate to nourish and retain those whom they were
afraid they would beget. This infliction of cruelty on their offspring, so
reluctantly begotten, unmasks the sin which they had practised in darkness and
drags it clearly into the light of day. The open cruelty reproves the concealed
sin. Sometimes, indeed, this lustful cruelty, or cruel lust, resorts to such
extravagant methods as to use poisonous drugs to secure barrenness; or else, if
unsuccessful in this, to destroy the conceived seed by some means previous to
birth, preferring that its offspring should rather perish than receive
vitality; or if it was advancing in life within the womb, should be slain
before it was born. (De nupt. et conc., i.17)
Contraception
is linked with abortion and exposure insofar as it is practised as a means not
of 'family planning' but of family prevention or family destruction. In this
context, it serves as a hrst line of defence against the disaster of the
'unwanted pregnancy', that is, of the unwanted child. If this fails, a second
line of defence is available: the child in the womb may be surgically removed.
(If that is its appointed destiny, it is described as a 'foetus'.) If this too
fails or is omitted, the child may be abandoned after birth. The disadvantage
of this method in comparison to the others lies in its 'open cruelty'. The
secret shame of concupiscence, which in a marriage open to procreation is
restrained and put to good use, issues here in the public shame of abandoning a
fellow human being to the mercy of the fates and the elements. It is
understandable that public opinion should favour the destruction of unwanted
children at an earlier stage, when concealment is still possible; but even
where the third line of defence is abandoned, the defensive strategy to which
it belonged remains intact. Contraception and abortion together preserve the
hegemony of sex. They protect the integrity of paradise by promising that the
couple who become one flesh there will not have to face any undesirable consequences.
Although the concupiscence that rules this paradise is also present in the
sphere of marital fidelity and the family (‘planned’ or otherwise), it does not
rule there. Within the sphere of its hegemony, concupiscence ‘plays the king in
the foul indulgences of adultery, fornication, lasciviousness and uncleanness,
whereas in the indisputable duties of the married state it shows the docility
of the slave’ (De nupt. et conc., i.13).
The prohibition,
‘Thou shalt not lust’ (non concupisces) is the basis for Augustine’s
depiction of concupiscentia as a corruption of the human nature that was
created male and female. But, as Paul argues, the problem about this
prohibition is that it is counterproductive (Rom. 7.7-9). Despite its own
intentions, it serves only to promote the concupiscentia it prohibits.
It is integral to the paradise-like hegemony of sex to be illicit. Like
the serpent in Genesis 3, sin can use even the holy, just and good commandment
of God to further its own ends.
But
sin, finding its opportunity through the commandment, worked in me every kind
of desire. Apart from the law sin lies dead. I was once alive apart from the
law; but when the commandment came sin sprang to life and I died. (vv. 8-9) Sin used
the commandment to produce in me every kind of desire (v. 8). Here the claim of
verse 5 is repeated, that ‘the passions of sins were through the law at
work in our members . . . ’ But although the law is instrumental in the genesis
of sin, it is not the active agent in this process. The law is indeed
‘counterproductive’, but it does not ‘produce’ the sin it de®nes and condemns
by itself. It is sin itself, the orientation towards sin that is latent before
the law, that makes itself manifest in sinful desires or actions provoked by
the law. The law’s prohibition awakens a previously dormant rebellion or
resentment, which expresses itself in a desire for the illicit not because it
is necessarily desirable in itself but simply because it is illicit. The young
Augustine and his friends steal the forbidden fruit because it is forbidden;
their latent adolescent resistance to authority is aroused not by the fruit in
itself but by the fact that it is prohibited. The sin that is merely latent
apart from the commandment becomes manifest through the commandment.
Sin is
like the serpent in the Garden of Eden, who uses the commandment prohibiting
the fruit of the tree of the knowledge of good and evil to evoke desire for
that fruit. But in the Garden of Eden it is eating that was prohibited, not
desiring. The commandment, ‘You shall not desire’, was promulgated not in Eden
but at Sinai. It was ‘when the commandment came’ (elthouses de tes entoles)
that ‘sin revived and I died . . . ’ (vv. 9-10), and the coming of the
commandment can only be that event in which ‘law came in [pareiselthen]
so that the trespass [to para- ptoma] might increase’ (5.20). Sin was
dead ‘apart from law’ (7.8), and I was once alive ‘apart from law’ (7.9). There
was therefore a time before the coming of the commandment, the time ‘from Adam
to Moses’ (5.14) during which, in the absence of law, sin was ‘not counted’
(5.13). In Eden, there was no such time before the commandment. It is true that
the coming of the commandment brought death to one who previously lived
(7.9—11), whereas from Adam to Moses ‘death reigned’ even though sin was not
counted (5.14). But in both passages the point is that the law made the
situation of humanity after Adam worse rather than better. In the earlier
passage, the situation becomes worse because through the law ‘the trespass’ —
Adam’s trespass — ‘increased’. Before Moses, people did not sin ‘in the
likeness of Adam’s transgression [parabasis]’ (5.14); after Moses they
did so, in the sense that they now sinned in conscious deHance of an explicit
divine commandment. The coming of the law can therefore be seen as a
re-enactment of the story of the Fall, a second transition from life to death.
If the ministry of Moses is a ‘ministry [diakonia] of death’ (2 Cor.
3.7), and if ‘the letter kills’ (v. 6), then the people of Israel who received
this ‘letter’ in the form of‘stone tablets’ (v. 7) must have been ‘alive’
before the glorious ministry of Moses brought death to them.[xlvii]
According
to Romans 7, ‘the letter’ brought death to the people of Israel because it
provoked the very sin it prohibited. The coming of the commandment, ‘You shall
not desire’, aroused every kind of desire for forbidden objects, and sin led to
death (dia tes hamartias ho thanatos, 5.12). We shall in due course
answer the question why the hrst person singular is used in this passage. The
hrst task is to show in more detail how it can credibly be understood as a
rehection on Israel’s experience in the wilderness.15
At
Sinai, the commandment came: ‘You shall not desire’ (ouk
1980, 196); so too H. Schlier, Der Romerbrief
Herders theologischer Kommentar zum Neuen Testament, Freiburg im Breisgau:
Herder, 1977, 223 ('Dieses Geschehen ist die Geschichte Adams, den jeder Mensch
in seiner Existenz im Nachvollzug der Sunde prasent macht’); U. Wilckens, Der
Brief an die Romer, Evangelisch-katholischer Kommentar zum Neuen Testament,
Zurich, Einsiedeln, Cologne: Benziger/Neu- kirchener Verlag, 1980, 2.79 ('in
der Geschichte des ''Ich’’ wird Adams Geschichte je existentiell konkret’). In
opposition to this, N. T. Wright rightly argues that 'the primary emphasis of
the argument is on Israel, not Adam: what is being asserted about Israel is
that when the Torah arrived it had the same effect on her as God’s commandment
in the Garden had on Adam’ (The Climax of the Covenant: Christ and the Law
in Pauline Theology, Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1991, 197). See also D. J.
Moo, 'Israel and Paul in Rom. 7.7 — 12’, NTS 32 (1986), 122 — 35. The
shortcomings of the 'Adamic’ reading of this passage are also noted by R. H.
Gundry, 'The Moral Frustration of Paul before his Conversion: Sexual Lust in
Romans 7:7—25’, in Pauline Studies: Essays presented to F. F. Bruce, ed.
D. A. Hagner and M. J. Harris, Exeter: Paternoster, 1980, 228—45; 230—2.
15 Does
Paul in Rom. 7.7—13 consciously 'intend’ the intertextual links with passages
in the Psalms and the Pentateuch that are explored in what follows, and does he
'intend’ to communicate these links to his readers? Richard Hays identifies
five possible explanations for the phenomenon of the textual 'echo’, the
hermeneutical event of a textual fusion: the event occurs in the mind of the
author, in the original readers, in the text itself, in the act of reading, in
a community of interpretation (Echoes of Scripture in the Letters of Paul,
New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1989, 26). Rather than aligning
himself with any one of these hermeneutical options, Hays wishes to 'hold them
all together in creative tension’ (27). 'The hermeneutical event occurs in my
reading of the text, but my reading always proceeds within a community of
interpretation, whose hermeneutical conventions inform my reading. Prominent
among these conventions are the convictions that a proposed interpretation
must be justihed with reference to evidence provided both by the text’s
rhetorical structure and by what can be known through critical investigation
about the author and original readers. Any interpretation must respect these
constraints in order to be persuasive within my reading community’ (28). My own
claim is that Rom. 7.7—13 can be read, credibly and naturally, against the
background of narrative texts in the Pentateuch and the Psalter. Beyond that,
we are in the realm of supposition: I assume that this intertextual matrix was
not far from Paul’s mind as he wrote, and that the more perceptive among his
hrst readers might have recognized this. epithumeseis). Did it
really provoke ‘every kind of desire’ (pasan epithumian)? Israel’s
experience in the wilderness was indeed an experience of desire. According to
Psalms 105.14-15, ‘They desired [with] desire in the wilderness [kai
epethumesan epithumian en te eremo], and they tested God in the desert. And
he gave them what they asked, and sent fullness [plesmonen] into their
souls.’ The reference is to Numbers 11, where it is said that
the
rabble that was among them desired [with] desire [epethumesan epithumian],
and seating themselves the sons of Israel wept and said, Who will give us meat
to eat? We remember [emnesthemen] the fish that we ate in Egypt for
nothing, and the cucumbers, melons, leeks, onions and garlic; but now our soul
is dried up, and there is nothing but manna before our eyes. (vv. 4—6)
In
response, the Lord promises to provide the people with meat every day for a month,
until they are sick of it — ‘because they disobeyed [epeithesate] the
Lord who is among you’ (vv. 18—20). A wind from the Lord brings a glut of
quails, which the people gather (vv. 31—2). But
while
the meat was still between their teeth, before it was consumed, the Lord was
angry with the people and the Lord smote the people with a very great plague.
And the name of that place was called Tombs-of-Desire [Mnemata tes
Epithumias], because there they buried the people who had desired [ton
laon ton epithumeten]. From Tombs-of- Desire [apo MnematOn Epithumias]
the people journeyed to Aseroth, and the people were in Aseroth. (vv. 33—5)
The
memorials to desire are mentioned again in Numbers 33.16—17, in the context of
an itinerary that takes the people of Israel from Egypt to the plains of Moab
(vv. 1—49), and in Deuteronomy 9.22, where Moses reminds the people how ‘at
Conflagration [en to Empurismd] and at Testing [en to Peirasmd] and
at Tombs-of-Desire [en tois Mnemasin tes Epithumias] you angered the
Lord your God’. (‘Conflagration’ is ‘Taberah’, so called because there ‘a fire
from the Lord’ [pur para kuriou] burned among the people (Num. 11.3).
‘Testing’ (cf. Deut. 6.16) is ‘Massah’, where the people of Israel put the Lord
to the test by demanding water; its full name is Testing-and-Abuse [Peir-
asmos kai Loidoresis], ‘because of the abuse [loidorian] of the sons
of Israel and because they tested the Lord [dia to peirazein kurion], saying,
Is the Lord among us or not?’ (Ex. 17.7).) The brief reference to these
ill-fated places in Deuteronomy 9.22 occurs in the context of the claim that
the people will inherit the promised land not on account of their righteousness
but in spite of their stubborn and rebellious heart (Deut. 9.1-10.11); the
incident of the Golden Calf is narrated here at length. Thus ‘desire’ takes its
place in a narrative of rebellion against God that is also characterized by
idolatry and by ‘testing’. As in Romans 7.9—11, desire leads to death — a fact
that is commemorated in the place-name, ‘Tombs-of-Desire’. The people who
desired remembered the rich food of Egypt, but they themselves were remembered
only in the form of the warning embedded in the place-name. The link between
desire and death is especially clear in Psalms 77.26—31:
He
caused an east wind to blow from heaven, and led out the south wind by his
power. And he rained upon them flesh like dust, winged birds like the sand of
the seas, and made them fall in the midst of their camp, around their tents.
And they ate and were well satisfied, for he brought them their desire [ten
epithumian auton]. They were not rid of their desire [apo tes epithumias
auton], their food was still in their mouths, when the wrath of God [he
orge tou theou] fell upon them; he killed [apekteinen] as they drank,
as the elect [tous eklektous] of Israel danced together.
Even for
the elect of Israel, desire leads to death. As in Romans 7.7—11, the desire
that leads to death is rebellion against God.
In 1 Corinthians
10.6—11, Paul himself describes Israel’s experience in the wilderness in terms
of desire and death. Here, ‘desire’ is no longer tied to the single incident of
the quails. A number of incidents of rebellion and death in the wilderness
substantiate the warning that we are not to be ‘desirers of evil things [epithumetas
kakon], as they desired [epethumesan]’ (v. 6). Desire issues, ®rst,
in idolatry, the making of the Golden Calf together with the revelry that
accompanied it: ‘The people sat to eat and drink and rose to play’ (v. 7,
quoting Ex. 32.6). Desire issues, second, in porneia. ‘We must not
commit fornication, as some of them committed fornication, and twenty-three
thousand fell in one day’ (v. 8). The reference is to another instance of
idolatry, when ‘the people profaned itself by committing fornication [ekporneusai]
with the daughters of Moab. They invited them to the sacri®ces of their idols,
and the people ate of their sacri®ces and worshipped their idols' (Num.
25.1—2). Twenty-four thousand people died in the ensuing plague (v. 9), which
was halted by the zeal of Phinehas, who pierced an Israelite man and a Moabite
woman through the body with a single thrust of his spear, as they engaged in
the sexual act (vv. 6—8). Desire issues, third, in ‘putting the Lord [or, the
Christ] to the test, as some of them put him to the test and were destroyed by
snakes' (1 Cor. 10.9). On this occasion, ‘the people spoke against God and
against Moses, saying, Why did you bring us out from Egypt, to kill us in the
wilderness? For there is no bread or water, and our soul is tired of this
worthless food' (Num. 21.5). The plague of snakes that followed was halted by
the setting up of a bronze snake on a pole, which brought healing to those who
looked at it (v. 9). It is not explicitly said here that those who spoke against
God and Moses ‘put the Lord to the test'. But in Numbers 14.22 it is said that
the people ‘have put me to the test these ten times, and have not listened to
my voice' — indicating that ‘putting the Lord to the test' by making demands of
him is a constant theme of these narratives. ‘They tested him again and again,
and provoked the Holy One of Israel' (Ps. 78(77).4). Finally, desire issues in
complaining: ‘Do not complain, as some of them complained and were destroyed by
the destroyer' (1 Cor. 10.10). Shortly after their deliverance at the Red Sea,
the people begin to ‘complain' about their lot (Ex. 15.24, 16.7—12); Exodus
17.2—3 indicates that ‘complaining' against Moses cannot be sharply
distinguished from ‘putting the Lord to the test'. But it is only after the
giving of the law at Sinai that this tendency to complain leads to destruction.
In Numbers 14, the complaints that follow the report of the spies (v. 2) lead
to the divine proclamation that the present generation of Israelites will, with
just two exceptions, perish in the wilderness (vv. 26—35). In Numbers 16, the
Levites' complaints against Aaron's priestly prerogatives (v. 11) result in the
destruction of Korah, Dathan and Abiram and their company. When the people
complain that ‘you have killed the people of the Lord' (v. 41), the killing
continues as a plague destroys many more people. In each of these incidents of
idolatry, immorality, testing and complaining, the people of Israel show
themselves to be ‘desirers of evil’ (1 Cor. 10.6). All of these narratives are
‘memorials of desire’ (Mnemata tes Epithumias). They warn their readers
not to desire the evil that the Israelites once desired.
According
to Romans 7.7—9, ‘I was once alive apart from the commandment’; at that time,
‘sin lay dead’. But then ‘the commandment came’ — the commandment, ‘You shall
not desire’ — with the result that ‘sin, taking opportunity through the
commandment, worked in me every kind of desire’. Initially, I was alive and sin
was dead; but through the law, sin came to life and I died. We have seen that
in 1 Corinthians 10 Paul presents Israel’s experience in the wilderness as a
history of evil desire — extending a theme that in the Pentateuch is conhned to
the single incident in Numbers 11. Although in 1 Corinthians 10 Paul does not
imply that the law was instrumental in generating this desire, the reduction of
the tenth commandment to a general prohibition of desire in Romans 7.7 creates
a link with his earlier reading of the wilderness narratives as a history of
desire. The examples of idolatry, porneia, testing and complaining that
he selects all follow the giving of the law, for it is only from Sinai
onwards that Israel’s rebellious actions have the destructive consequences that
Paul emphasizes. It is true that incidents of putting the Lord to the test and
of complaining occur before as well as after the event at Sinai. But idolatry
and porneia occur only afterwards; they are closely associated in the
Pentateuchal stories (Ex. 32 and Num. 25), which tell of two occasions when the
people transgress the first and second commandments, and when transgression
leads to death. In these events, ‘the letter kills’; the ministry of Moses
turns out to be a ‘ministry of death’ (2 Cor. 3.6—7). But the law does not kill
of itself. ‘It was sin, working death in me through what was good . . . ’ (Rom.
7.13). ‘Sin, ®nding opportunity in the commandment, deceived me and by it
killed me’ (7.11): it is this event that is commemorated in the place-name — in
Latin, Sepulchra Concupiscentiae. The latent sin of the people, hardly a
signihcant factor prior to the revelation at Sinai, expresses itself
immediately afterwards in actions that wilfully transgress the commandments. In
Paul’s reading of this history, the fact of the divine prohibition has the
effect of making idolatry and the porneia that is associated with it desirable.
In these acts, a latent resistance to the God of the exodus and of the fathers,
of which the testing and complaining are already symptomatic, becomes manifest
and visible in crude acts of deHance. For Paul, it is the law itself which, by
prohibiting desire, actually provokes the desire that comes to expression in
the demand, ‘Up, make us gods who shall go before us; as for this man Moses,
who brought us out of Egypt, we do not know what has become of him’ (Ex. 32.1).
The claim that sinful passions operate in our members ‘through the law’ (Rom.
7.5) is an attempt to explain how a people who at Sinai solemnly attest, ‘All
that the Lord has spoken we will do and hear’ (Ex. 24.7) are shortly afterwards
practising porneia and idolatry with the daughters of Moab (Num.
25.1-2).
The law
of God provokes a resistance in the sinful human heart that issues in acts
where what is desired is the transgression itself: that is the theme both of
Augustine’s autobiographical reading of the incident of the pear tree and of
Paul’s autobiographical reading of the history of Israel in the wilderness.
This ‘autobiographical’ dimension of the Pauline narrative now requires closer
attention.
EGG AND ALTER EGG [VERSES 10± 25)
I
found that the commandment that promised life brought me death. For sin, ®nding
its opportunity through the commandment, deceived me and through it killed me. (vv. 10-11) As in
the preceding verses, motifs from Genesis 2—3 are visible here. As the serpent
in the Garden of Eden found in the divine commandment the opportunity it needed
to deceive the Hrst human couple and to bring about their death, so in this
Hrst-person narrative the pattern of the Fall is re-enacted. In confessing how
sin ‘deceived me’ (exepatesen me), the speaker identiHes himself with
Eve, who confessed that ‘the serpent deceived me [epatesen me]’ (Gen.
3.13). ‘As the serpent deceived [exepatesen] Eve by his cunning’ (2 Cor.
11.3), so now sin has ‘deceived me’. Yet, as we have seen, the nexus of life,
death, sin and the commandment relates primarily to the history of Israel in
the wilderness. It cannot be said of the single commandment in the Garden of
Eden that it promised life. It was a commandment ‘unto life’ (eis zoen)
only in the very general sense that observing it allowed Adam and Eve unhindered
access to the tree of life. The commandment that is ‘unto life’ is the Law of
Moses, for it is promised here that ‘the person who observes these things will
live by them [zosetai en autois]’ (Lev. 18.5, quoted in Rom. 10.5, Gal.
3.12). Thus the speaker’s experience re-enacts the pattern of the Fall only
insofar as this is projected onto the history of Israel in the wilderness.
Motifs from Genesis help to interpret this history, in which Adam’s
transgression comes to fruition (Rom. 5.12-14, 20); but the hrst person
narrative cannot be read simply as a retelling of the Genesis story. The
speaker is identihed with Eve or Adam only insofar as Israel is.
At the beginning of
Romans 7, second person plural verbs are used in addressing predominantly
Gentile readers (v. 1, 4ab). In verses 4c-6, Paul identihes himself with his
readers by shifting to the hrst person plural. With the exception only of ‘what
then shall we say?’ (v. 7) and ‘we know that the law is spiritual’ (v. 14),
verses 7-25 are consistent in their use of the hrst person singular, which has
previously occurred only in ‘I speak to those who know the law’ (v. 1) and in
‘my brothers’ (v. 4). If the speaker is in some sense Paul himself, then he
must be speaking in a representative capacity; his hrst person discourse would
have no bearing on his claim that ‘we’ are freed from ‘the oldness of the
letter’ (v. 6) if he were speaking of a purely individual experience. Since it
is the history of Israel in the wilderness that is retold in this hrst person
narrative, Paul must be speaking as a representative of Israel. Elsewhere in
this letter, he speaks of himself not only as a slave and apostle of Jesus
Christ (1.1) but also as ‘an Israelite, of the seed of Abraham and the tribe of
Benjamin’ (11.1). As such, he represents in his own person the fact that ‘God
has not rejected his people whom he foreknew’ (11.2); for the ‘Israelites’, to
whom belong ‘the sonship and the glory and the covenants and the giving of the
law and the worship and the promises’, are ‘my brethren’ and ‘my kinsmen
according to the flesh’ (9.3—4). In chapter 7, he can therefore speak as a
representative Jew in whom Israel’s initial highly ambivalent experience of the
law is re-enacted.
Yet the
event at Sinai is for Paul universal in its scope. The situation of Jews under
the law discloses the situation of the world. In the first person story of the
Jewish narrator in Romans 7, Gentiles such as Augustine can also read their own
stories. The story that is told is a tragic story, the story of a catastrophe.
It explains how it came about that one who is the privileged recipient of ‘the
words of God’ (3.2) is nevertheless condemned as a transgressor by those same
divine words, over and over again (3.9—20). The divine words that point the way
to life have led only to death, because sin, finding its opportunity through
the commandment, deceived me and worked in me sin and death. The Israelite who
speaks here is closely related to the earlier figure of the Jew who zealously
teaches the law to those who are in darkness and yet transgresses its
commandments himself (2.17—24). But he is also related to the ‘man’ (whether
Gentile or Jew) who judges another: ‘For in passing judgment on him you condemn
yourself, because you, the judge, are doing the very same things’ (2.1). Every
attempt to live righteously in an unrighteous world is subverted by the fact
that ‘all have sinned’ (3.23); this attempt and its failure become visible in
the figure of a Jew such as Paul himself, but, once identified, the pattern can
also be traced elsewhere. The Pharisee and the taxcollector in the temple are
hardly exclusively Jewish ®gures.
The
tragedy or catastrophe, presented so starkly on page after page of Jewish
scripture, is embraced within a divine comedy: ‘Where sin increased, grace
abounded all the more’ (Rom. 5.20). The speaker in chapter 7 is not only an
Israelite who must tell how the divine gift led to his death; he is also an apostle
called to proclaim a God who raises the dead. The Israelite and the apostle are
one. The story-teller who narrates the divine comedy must also be capable of
narrating the human tragedy, if he is to show how in Jesus (another Israelite)
the divine grace and mercy have triumphed over human sin. In Jesus, the
‘oldness of the letter’ has been embraced and surpassed in the ‘newness of the
Spirit’ (v. 6). As his sad story reaches its conclusion, the story-teller will
therefore lament and give thanks as if in a single breath: ‘Wretched man that I
am! Who will deliver me from the body of this death? Thanks be to God through
Jesus Christ our Lord!’ (vv. 24-5).
So
the law is holy and the commandment is holy and just and good. Did what is good
bring death to me, then? Certainly not! It was sin, so that it might be exposed
as sin, that worked death in me through what is good, so that sin might become
exceedingly sinful through the commandment. (vv. 12-13) The law does not
generate sin of itself. It is sin - latent sin — which uses the law to make
itself manifest. Thus the law itself is good, and cannot be held responsible
for its disastrous consequences, beginning with the cycle of rebellion and
punishment that characterized Israel’s experience in the wilderness. If,
because of the sin latent in the human heart, the law provokes the sin that it
forbids and is therefore the bringer of death rather than life, that does not
detract from its divine glory. If it can be said that the glory of the law has
now been eclipsed by a glory that surpasses it (2 Cor. 3.7—11), the reason is
that the ‘life’ and ‘righteousness’ that the law intends are now fulhlled in
the resurrection of Jesus Christ, so that the judgment pronounced by the law is
not God’s last word to humankind. The contrast between ‘the oldness of the
letter’ and ‘the newness of the Spirit’ (Rom. 7.6) disparages not the law but
the human sin that not only fails to obey the law but also uses it to further
its own rebellious purposes. The law’s inability of itself to place humankind
on the way to life is the result not just of human weakness but of human
malice. If‘the power of sin is the law’ (1 Cor. 15.56), this is an indictment
not of the law but of the sinful human heart. ‘The heart is deceitful above all
things, and desperately corrupt; who can understand it?’ (Jer. 17.9). It is the
deceitful human heart that uses even the divine gift of the law at Sinai as an
occasion for sin, and that necessitates a ‘new covenant’ in which the intention
of the old, that ‘I will be their God and they shall be my people’, is at last
fulhlled (31.31—3). It is fulhlled through a death and a resurrection: ‘You
have died to the law through the body of Christ, so that you may belong to
another, to the one who has been raised from the dead so that we may bear fruit
for God’ (Rom. 7.4). In Christ’s death, the deceitful human heart is
‘condemned’ (Rom. 8.3). The new covenant is therefore ‘the new covenant in my
blood’ (1 Cor. 11.25). In Christ’s resurrection, we are incorporated through
the Spirit into his own life of bearing fruit for God. The new covenant is
therefore the work of the life-giving Spirit (2 Cor. 3.6). Jesus is the
‘Israelite’ in whom the promise that ‘I will be your God and they shall be my
people’ is fulhlled; God is therefore ‘the God and Father of our Lord Jesus
Christ’ (15.6) and Jesus is ‘his Son’ (1.3, 8.3). It is this covenantal
relationship into which we are incorporated through the Spirit, so that we too
address God as ‘Abba, Father’ (8.15).
In this covenantal
relationship, the law is surpassed and superseded insofar as, in itself, it
represents the ‘ministry of death’ (2 Cor. 3.7). But its commandment remains
‘holy and just and good’ (Rom. 7.12). It still identihes the pattern of human
conduct that conforms to the will of God and that is ‘good and acceptable and
perfect’ before God (12.2). Christian agape is the love for the
neighbour that fulhls the law and that is variously expressed in the individual
commandments: You shall not commit adultery, you shall not kill, you shall not
steal, you shall not desire (13.8-10). The idolatry and porneia that the
law forbids but unwittingly provokes are also forbidden within the new
covenant, where the imperatives are no less uncompromising. ‘Flee from
idolatry’ (1 Cor. 10.14). ‘Flee immorality’ (6.18). In showing how the new
covenant takes up this pattern of conduct, which in itself leads only to sin
and death when exposed to the deceitful human heart, ‘we affirm the law’ rather
than annulling it (3.31).
For
we know that the law is spiritual, but I am carnal, sold under sin. For what I
do I do not recognize; for I do not do what I want, but I do what I hate. If I
do what I do not want, I accept that the law is good, and it is now no longer I
that do it but sin dwelling within me. (vv. 14-17) Indwelling, latent
sin has used what is good in order to manifest itself in sinful actions that
lead to death (v. 13). This is a past event that occurred at Sinai and that has
its correlate in the speaker’s past life. The catastrophe at Sinai, where the
deceitful human heart learned to further its own ends through the divine
commandment, was not a matter for the wilderness generation alone; it is a
paradigm of Israel's entire history with God as presented in the scriptural
record, and the individual Israelite is therefore implicated in it. Since
Israel's history with God represents human history with God, it can be said
that what is disclosed at Sinai is simply ‘human nature' — not the human nature
that Adam and Eve received from God, but the human nature that they passed on
to their descendants.
In the
shift to the present tense, the narrator begins to speak of the life he now
lives in the shadow of the catastrophe. This narrator is Paul, a Jew who
confesses: ‘I am an Israelite, of the seed of Abraham and the tribe of
Benjamin' (ii.i). The ego eimi of
that confession is identical to the ego eimi of 7.14: ‘I am carnal, sold
under sin'. Paul is an Israelite who is also an apostle of Jesus Christ, but
for the present the first aspect of his vocation is considered in abstraction
from the second. He knows that he is carnal, sold under sin, because the law
tells him so. He has heard the words of condemnation that the law addresses to
‘those who are under the law', and he acknowledges the law's verdict on behalf
of‘the whole world', ‘all flesh' (3.19—20). He affirms the goodness of the law
as embodying the divine will for humankind, he disowns the hostility and
resistance to God that the law evoked in his corrupt heart — and yet he must
also confess that traces of this hostility and resistance are everywhere
evident in his own conduct. Having learned from the law about his true
situation, he is in no position to ‘establish a righteousness ofhis own'
(10.3) but echoes the confession of Daniel:
O
Lord, the great and terrible God, who keepest covenant and steadfast love with
those who love him and keep his commandments, we have sinned and done wrong and
acted wickedly and rebelled, turning aside from thy commandments and
ordinances. We have not listened to thy servants the prophets, who spoke in thy
name to our kings, our princes and our fathers, and to all the people of the
land. To thee, O Lord, belongs righteousness, but to us confusion of face . . .(Dn.
9.4—7)
In his
confession, the Israelite represents a mid-point between the deceitful heart,
in which the divine gift of the law serves only to evoke resistance and
hostility to God, and the new covenant established in the death and
resurrection of Jesus, who is also an Israelite (Rom. 9.4). The confession is a
confession of what one is and of what human nature is, yet in the
act of confession what one is is relegated to the past; what one is
is now the person who confesses what one was but is no longer. ‘I
do what I hate’ (7.15): the ‘I’ that performs the evil action is supplanted by
the ‘I’ that hates this action because it contravenes the law which is
acknowledged as holy and just and good. From the standpoint of this confession,
‘it is now no longer I that do it but sin dwelling within me’ (v. 17).
The law provides no escape from this dialectic of sin and repentance; yet, in
the retrospective light of the new covenant, it becomes clear that the
problematic self-knowledge expressed in it is integral to the testimony of the
law and the prophets to ‘the righteousness of God through the faith ofJesus
Christ’ (3.21-2).
For I
know that nothing good dwells within me, that is, within my flesh. For to will
is possible for me, but to do what is good is not. For I do not do the good I
want, but the evil I do not want is what I do. If I do what I do not want, it
is no longer I that do it but sin dwelling within me. (vv. 18-20) ‘I know
that nothing good dwells within me . . . ’ is parallel to ‘I am carnal, sold
under sin’ in v. 14, which opens with a statement of what ‘we know’. This is
the knowledge of human nature, exemplihed in one’s own person, that corresponds
to the discovery that I do what I do not want. The moment of discovery is the
moment of confession, and in this account willing is tied to that moment. ‘The
good I want’ is the good I want in the moment of confession. To confess that
‘we have left undone those things which we ought to have done and done those
things which we ought not to have done’ is already to will the good and to
acknowledge the gulf between present willing and past doing. But only in that
moment of confession does a willing arise that critically detaches itself from
doing. It cannot be the speaker’s view that in the human person there coexist
in parallel an unwilled, involuntary action and an impotent willing of a quite
different action, as though the self were trapped in a machine over which it
has no control. Action is always voluntary, willed action; involuntary
responses to a stimulus are not 'action'. The willing that in confession
detaches itself from action denies not that action was willed but that I
— the ego that is now the subject of confession ± willed it. In
confession, the willing that accompanied the action that one now 'hates' is
disowned and attributed to an alter ego that is not-I but 'sin dwelling
within me'. Yet when I act I am the subject of my actions; I identify myself
again with the alter ego I disowned, and I no longer hate my actions or
myself as the subject of my actions.16
This
dialectic of sin and repentance appears to arise from an original encounter
with the law in which sin sprang to life and I died. The sin that once found
its opportunity in the law and by it killed me is the sin that still dwells
within me and subverts my willing of the good that the law intends. Despite the
seamless continuity of the narrative, however, the view that it is distinctively
Christian experience that is depicted in Rom. 7.i4±25 has remained
influential.17 Augustine explains how he reached that conclusion:
It
had once appeared to me too that the apostle was in this argument of his
describing a man under the law. But afterwards I was compelled to give up the
idea by those words where he says, ‘Now then it is no longer I that do it' ±
for to this corresponds what he later says, 'There is therefore now no
condemnation to those who are in Christ Jesus' — and also because I do not see
how a man under the law could say, 'I delight in the law of God after the
inward man', since this very delight in good . . . can only be attributed to
grace. (Con. duas epist., i.22)
Augustine
maintains this view over against the Pelagian claim that the passage depicts
the person under the law. In his De
16 In Augustine's reading, willing the
good and doing the evil are simultaneous because it is the tenth commandment,
forbidding concupiscentia, that is at the same time affirmed and
transgressed. Although I shall follow Augustine's reading of vv. 21—3 in terms
of Gen. 3, I do not think that the conflict described in vv. 14—23 can be
confined to epithumia and the tenth commandment if the text is read on
its own terms.
17 Cranfield approvingly cites Calvin's
comment, that in this passage Paul ‘is depicting in his own person the
character and extent of the weakness of believers' (Romans, 1.356); see
also A. Nygren, Commentary on Romans [1944], ET London: SCM Press, 1952,
284—303; John Murray, The Epistle to the Romans, New International
Commentary on the New Testament, Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1959, where 7.14 — 25
is entitled 'the contradiction in the believer' (256). gratia Christi, he
quotes Pelagius’ own interpretation of the passage, taken from a dialogue with
an Augustinian opponent. Pelagius writes:
Now,
that which you wish us to understand of the apostle himself, all church writers
assert that he spoke in the person of the sinner, and of one who was still
under the law — such a man as was, because vice had long been customary with
him, held bound, as it were, by a certain necessity of sinning, and who
although he desired good with his will in practice indeed was rushed headlong
into evil. In the person, however, of one man, the apostle designates the
people who still sinned under the ancient law. This nation he declares was to
be delivered from this evil of custom through Christ, who first of all remits
all sins in baptism to those who believe in him, and then urges them by an
imitation of himself to perfect holiness, and by the example of his own virtues
overcomes the evil custom of their sins. (De grat. Chr., i.43)
On any
reading, the passage is a problem for Pelagius, for whom the freedom originally
bestowed on Adam must still survive unimpaired. Although Pelagius does not
admit this, the ‘man under the law’ is on his view labouring under a misapprehension.
This man believes that the habit of sin makes sin necessary, failing to
recognize that he still retains the freedom to break with that habit. He is, in
effect, an Augustinian. In other words, the passage opposes the Pelagian
position whether the speaker is held to be a Christian or a Jew. The only
advantage Pelagius derives from his claim that the apostle speaks here as a
person under the law is that this makes it possible to contradict him.
Augustine’s claim
that ‘delight in the law’ is inconceivable for the ‘man under law’ is
contradicted by Jewish scripture, where the hostility to the law that runs
through the history of Israel is always presented from a standpoint of loyalty
to the law as the law of God. Israel’s ambivalence towards the law stems from
its position on the boundary between the corrupted human nature of the
‘deceitful heart’ and the human nature renewed in and through the obedience
ofJesus.
This
is what I discover, then, about the law: that when I will the good, evil is
present to me. For I delight in the law of God in my inner self, but I see
another law in my members, fighting against the law my mind acknowledges, and
making me captive to the law of sin that is in my members. (vv. 21-3) The
conflict between willing the good and doing the evil is now redescribed as a
conflict between the law of God acknowledged by the mind and the law of sin
acknowledged by my members. This conflict is described as a discovery about the
law, which does not give me the capacity to resist those imperatives of the
body that it denounces as sinful.[xlviii] The earlier reflection on the law’s involvement in
the origins of sin is here replaced by an emphasis on its powerlessness;
the law was ‘weak through the flesh’ (8.3). Yet the law that proves to be both
counterproductive and ineffectual remains the holy, just and good law of God, in
which the mind delights. It is counterproductive and ineffectual only in
abstraction from the new covenant in which it attains its true telos.
The precise content
of the good that is willed and the evil that is done has been left vague in the
preceding verses. In vv. 7—12, however, the entire law is summarized in the
single commandment, ‘You shall not desire’. Sexual desire — Augustine’s concupiscentia
— is for Paul the paradigmatic instance of the desire the law prohibits. This
makes it possible for Augustine to assume that ‘the law of sin that is in my
members’ is to be identified with concupiscence — the concupiscence that Adam
and Eve first experienced when they knew themselves to be naked:
When
the first man transgressed the law of God, he began to have another law in his
members which was repugnant to the law of his mind, and he felt the evil of his
own disobedience when he experienced in the disobedience of his own flesh a
most righteous retribution recoiling on himself. (De nupt. et conc.,
i.7)
The
Pauline text is read here as a commentary on the events narrated in Genesis 3,
the function of which is to point out that concupiscentia entails a loss
of control over the body, in the form of a reorganization of the body around
the genitals. Thus the overtly sexual dimension of the Genesis narrative is
interpreted along the lines of the Pauline text, which is accordingly interpreted
as an analysis of sexuality. In this intertextual relationship, each text
exercises a certain influence over the other as they are drawn into a
problematic that arises not from their individual sense but from their fusion.
The possibility of this fusion is suggested to Augustine by one small detail of
the Genesis text — the fact that, when Adam and Eve knew themselves to be
naked, they made themselves perizomata (Gen. 3.7), that is, garments
that concealed the genitals. This is an unexpected outcome of their
transgression:
If
those members by which sin was committed were to be covered after the sin, they
ought not indeed to have been clothed in loin-cloths [in tunicis] but to
have covered their hand and mouth, because they sinned by taking and eating.
What then is the meaning, when the prohibited food was taken and the
transgression of the commandment had been committed, of the look turned towards
those members? What unknown novelty is felt there and compels itself to be
noticed? (Con. duas epist., i.32)
The
answer is that the law of sin was already at work in their members, opposing
the law of their minds:
Since
they were suddenly so ashamed of their nakedness — which they had daily been in
the habit of seeing, but were not confused by it — that they could now no
longer bear those members naked, but immediately took care to cover them, did
they not — he in the visible motion [in motu aperto], she in the hidden
one [in occulto] — perceive those members to be disobedient to the
choice of their will, which certainly they ought to have ruled like the rest by
their voluntary command? And this they deservedly suffered, because they also
were not obedient to their Lord. Therefore they blushed that they had so failed
to serve their Creator that they should deserve to lose control over those
members by which children were to be procreated. (i.32)
This
lack of control is an anomaly within our bodily constitution:
It
is significant that the eyes, lips, tongue, hands and feet, the bending of the
back, neck and sides, are all subject to our power — to be applied to such
actions as are suitable to them, when we have a body free from physical
handicaps and in a sound state of health; but when it comes to man’s great
function in the procreation of children, the members which were expressly
created for this purpose will not obey the direction of the will, but lust has
to be awaited to set these members in motion, as if it had a legal right over
them - so that sometimes it refuses to act when the mind wills, while more
often it acts against its will. (De nupt. et conc., i.7)
Whether
through impotence or involuntary, unwelcome sexual arousal, the disobedient
male genitals evoke shame (in which the female genitals, their object,
are also implicated); and this shame is a symptom of the underlying cause of
shame, the human failure to worship and serve the Creator. In involuntary
sexual arousal, the ‘mind’ (nous) that ‘delights in the law of God’ may find
itself at odds with the ‘flesh’ (unlike the ‘mind [phronema] of the
flesh’ (Rom. 8.7) that is hostile to the law of God and delights in the law of
sin). At this point, the conflict between willing and doing (7.14-21) is traced
back to a conflict that precedes action - the conflict between the mind’s
acquiescence in the commandment, ‘You shall not desire’, and the
quasi-autonomous ‘desire’ through which the entire body is reoriented towards
the genitals and so reveals its humiliating subjection to the ‘law of sin’. It
is this conflict that causes Adam and Eve to be, for the first time, ashamed of
their nakedness and to hide the bodily parts on which that shame is focused.
Augustine’s phenomenology of sexuality shows that the link between sexuality
and shame is basic. Symptoms of this may be traced across a range of phenomena:
public conventions about ‘decency’ of clothing or speech; the uneasy pleasure
of sexual innuendo or jokes; anxieties about sexual ‘performance’; the
excitement and hostility aroused by other people’s sexual behaviour; the
voyeuristic obsession with the ‘sexually explicit’ image or word; the guilt
that often accompanies the practice of masturbation; the tensions that
surround the sex education of children; the intense emotional ambivalences
associated with the erect penis and female pubic hair. These and many other
inexplicable phenomena of sexuality — culturally variable though they may be -
are all symptoms of the Pauline and Augustinian ‘law of sin which is in my
members’.
Wretched
man that I am! Who will deliver me from the body of this death? Thanks be to
God through Jesus Christ our Lord! So then I myself serve the law of God with
the mind, but with the flesh the law of sin. (vv. 24-5) We have seen that
the apostle is speaking in this passage not as an apostle but as a ‘man under
the law’ who has attained disturbing insights into the complex relationship of
law and sin. But it is only as a Christian that he can impersonate this man.
Gentiles as well as Jews may attain insights that resemble the position of this
Pauline ‘man under the law’. (Epictetus wishes to convince his pupil that ‘he
is not doing what he wishes and is doing what he does not wish [ho thelei
oupoiei kai ho me theleipoiei] (Discourses, ii.26.4). Paul himself
envisages Gentiles whose conscience bears witness that the work of the law is
inscribed on their hearts, as it condemns or approves their conduct (Rom.
2.14—15).) But neither Jew nor Gentile has any reason to draw the radical
Pauline conclusions about the law itself - that the divine law, holy and just
and good though it is, is instrumental in establishing the possibility and
actuality of sin, which it is powerless to prevent. A veil (Moses’ veil)
conceals these bitter truths when the law is read week by week in the synagogue
(2 Cor. 3.14—15), and when its requirements are proclaimed by the Jewish
teacher (Rom. 2.17—24) or the Gentile moralist (Rom. 2.1—5). It is ‘when one
turns to the Lord’ that ‘the veil is taken away’ (2 Cor. 3.16), so that one
sees for the ®rst time what the corrupt human heart has made of the law — in
the dawning light of the knowledge of what the God of the new covenant has made
of the corrupt human heart, through Jesus and his Spirit.[xlix]
Insight
into ‘the oldness of the letter’ arises from knowledge of‘the newness of the
Spirit’ (Rom. 7.6) and of the one ‘who has been raised from the dead in order
that we may be fruitful for God’ (7.4). Within the sphere of the koinonia
established by the action of the triune God, the ‘law of sin’ is not only
unmasked but also overcome. The captive who in Romans 7 speaks from within the
narrow conhnes of his prison cell must hear the proclamation of his liberation:
There
is no condemnation now, for those who are in Christ Jesus: for the law of the
Spirit of life in Christ Jesus has freed you [se] from the law of sin and
death. For what was impossible for the law [to adunaton tou nomou], in
that it was weak through the flesh, God has done: sending his own Son in the
likeness of sinful flesh and as an offering for sin, he condemned sin in the
flesh, so that the law’s decree might be ful®lled in us, who walk not according
to the flesh but according to the Spirit. (Rom. 8.1-4)
Freedom
from the ‘law of sin’ that makes the body a ‘body of death’ is actualized
through the Spirit, on the basis of the divine condemnation of sin that occurs
in the human life, death and resurrection of Jesus. In his life, Jesus bears
the likeness of sinful flesh, although he himself is ‘without sin’ (2
Cor. 5.21). His life already expresses his solidarity with the ‘wretched man’
of Romans 7. In his death, Jesus identi®es himself so completely with the man
or woman under the dominion of the law of sin that he himself endures the
divine condemnation of that dominion: God ‘made him to be sin for us’ (2 Cor.
5.21). It is therefore ‘you’ — Christian readers, men or women, in Rome or
elsewhere — who ‘died to the law through the body of Christ’ (Rom. 7.5), and
who now participate in his risen life.
Paulus’, Zeitschrift fUr neutestamentliche
Wissenschaft 23 (1924), 123—40; 130 (see also Bultmann’s later article,
'Romans 7 and the Anthropology of Paul’ [1932], ET in Existence and Faith,
ed. S. Ogden, London: Collins, 1964, 147—57). In opposition to an autobiographical
reading and to the pietistic understanding of sin and guilt to which it gives
rise, Bultmann argues that sin is not a perceptible entity in the empirical
human life but the self-sufficient attempt, provoked by the law (cf. Rom.
7.7—8), to establish oneself in relationship with God — the attempt that is
exposed and renounced in the event of faith (135 — 6). In analysing the various
proposed identi®ca- tions of the speaker in Rom. 7.7—25 (there are 'at least
five’ of these, according to J. Fitzmyer, Romans, 463—5), it is
important to bear in mind that superficially similar solutions may differ from
one another both exegetically and theologically.
This knowledge of
the triune divine action breaks into the end of the lament, in the form of a
thanksgiving: 'Thanks be to God through Jesus Christ our Lord!' (Rom. 7.25). It
is true that, as Augustine says, the vestiges of concupiscentia will
only ®nally be eliminated in the renewal of the human body at the resurrection
of the dead. Until that day, the exhortation, 'Let not sin reign in your mortal
bodies, to make you obey their passions' (6.12) will never be redundant. Yet
the Christian community lives already on the basis of the divine act that has
condemned the corrupt and deceitful human heart and brought a new creation into
being. That is the reality acknowledged by the thanksgiving.
PART III
Sacramentum: Ephesians 5
A man
leaves his father and his mother and is joined to his wife, so that the two
become one flesh. This is not the only way in which man and woman belong
together, nor is it the primary way. But among the various aspects of their
belonging together, there is also this one: their becoming one flesh. Where
this event participates in the love of Christ that reconciles the church and
all things to himself, it may be said: sacramentum hoc magnum est. If
the veil marks the limit of eros in order to preserve the space of agape, there
is no corresponding limit of agape; for an agape deriving from the breadth and
length and height and depth of the love of Christ knows no limit but must
occupy this sphere too, the space of the eros of man and woman.
This space may
appear to be self-contained and self-sufficient, withdrawn from the eyes of
the profane — a sacred space within which sacrifices are performed that
celebrate the divinity of the flesh. But the flesh is not divine, and neither
is eros: these are creaturely realities, and their original goodness is that of
the creature. The agape that overflows into this space too exposes the
pretensions of pseudo-divinities and restores to them their proper creaturely
status, bringing harmony and proportion where there was previously wilfulness
and excess.
As Luce Irigaray
argues, sexual ethics must show how the two remain two and indeed are
constituted as two as they become one flesh. Their oneness is not the
dissolution of their twoness but a third that embraces them; an
undifferentiated oneness is a symptom of a male projection onto the other that
denies her personhood and refashions her in the image of its own need.
Unfortunately, Irigaray’s sensitivity to the irreducibility of male—female
difference is not matched by an awareness of the irreducibility of divine—human
difference: in eros, it is assumed, humanity is divinized and divinity
incarnated. Eros is transfigured, and male—female erotic oneness and difference
assume metaphysical importance. Something similar occurs in theology itself,
where the erotic relation is traced back to a gendered archetype in the
relation of God to the world or Christ to the church (Barth, von Balthasar).
But no such apotheosis of eros or gender occurs in the Pauline text to which
appeal is made (Eph. 5). The eros of man and woman is at best a parable — one
among many — of the divine—human agape disclosed in Jesus. Eros and gender
remain purely creaturely realities, but they too participate in the assumption
and transfiguration of the creature within the divine agape.
CHAPTER
FIVE
In order
to secure the space of agape, within which the speech of men and women with
each other corresponds to their speech to and from God, eros had to be limited.
His limit was marked by the veil ± a visible sign, bound to a particular
cultural context and questionable even there, of the invisible reality of a
boundary that must be established wherever there is ekklesia, in which
woman is not apart from man nor man from woman. In the Lord, the
belonging-together of man and woman is not an erotic relation. ‘Man’ and
‘woman’ are present here not as potential sexual partners, to be identihed as
such by way of the erotically charged look that seeks out the face and body
that might provide an answer to its insistent question, but as called in Christ
to be together in agape.
In the union of the
Christian with Christ, there is a fruitbearing for God that supersedes the
fruit-bearing for death that occurs under the law. The law’s prohibition of
desire is sin’s opportunity to generate every kind of prohibited desire; for
the divine law is the place where the possibility of human autonomy is
established. Yet the possibility of an autonomous desire subject only to its
own law is excluded by a death and a resurrection, through which the intent of
the law ± a pattern of human conduct oriented towards life rather than death ±
is fulhlled. The commandment, ‘You shall love your neighbour as yourself’ is
fulhlled as, in union with Christ and through the Spirit, there is
fruit-bearing for God. But the commandment in which the whole law is summarized
also has a negative counterpart: ‘You shall not desire.’ Space for agape is
again ensured by the exclusion of eros. Sexual desire is an expression of a law
of sin in my members that is at war with the law of my mind. This desire is,
however, a corrupted derivative of that mutual desire of man and woman to
belong to one another and, within this relationship, to ful®l the divine
command and permission to be nothing less than co-creators. The corruption of
this original goodness is not absolute, and in Christ the telos of this
work of co-creation or pro-creation is disclosed as death and resurrection.
In these
Pauline reflections, is eros the victim of slander and of caricature? Is there
a malicious blindness here to the greatness of eros, despite the testimony of
common human experience? What is at stake here is not a ‘negative’ view of
eros but the distinction between its goodness as the creature of God and the
claim to divinity that constitutes its corruption. As a creature of God, eros
may serve as a parable of the divinehuman relationship. In the union of man
and woman as ‘one flesh’, the relationship of Christ and the ekklesia
may be prophetically foreshadowed (Eph. 5.31-2). The kingdom of God is like a
sower going forth to sow, it is like a woman baking bread or searching for a
lost coin, it is like a man who finds a pearl of great price - and it is like
the erotic union that also belongs to human life as given by God. Sexual union
is neither more nor less like the kingdom of God than sowing or baking. If
there is a co-creation in the one case, there is equally a co-creation in the
others. But in all these cases, this is a maturely co-creation: sexual
union does not divinize the human creature any more than sowing or baking does,
nor does it bestow any participation in divinity. The celebration of eros as
divine is no less a sign of its corruption than is the shame that celebration
represses.
In the
work of Luce Irigaray, an ethic of sexual difference is set within the horizon
of a divine eros that bestows divinity on the man and woman who participate, as
two and as one, in the sexual act. This ethic is opposed to an understanding of
sexuality in which the female role is to ‘satisfy’ male ‘needs’ — which is a
denial of ‘difference’ in the sense that woman becomes the projection of man’s
self-image and lacks a subjectivity and personhood of her own. In Irigaray’s
ethics, ‘difference’ is not mere heterogeneity or indifference: it is both the
ground and the fruit of the belonging-together of man and woman that culminates
in sexual union. In setting the ethical act of man and woman within the horizon
of divinity, Irigaray has recourse to biblical and Christian terminology —
understood in a self-consciously ‘heterodox’ manner. This makes it possible to
reopen the question of the relation of agape and eros that her ‘eroticism’
forecloses.1
Following Irigaray’s
own intertextual practice, this interaction with her philosophy of eros will
take the form of a ‘reading’ of a chapter of one of her texts — the
introductory reflections on ‘Sexual Difference’ in her An Ethics of Sexual
Difference.2
THE DOMINION OF EROS
'Sexual
difference is one of the major philosophical issues, if not the issue, of our
age. According to Heidegger, each age has one issue to think through, and one
only. Sexual difference is probably the issue in our time which could be our
"salvation” if we thought it through'. (Ethics, 5)
1 Reading Irigaray in terms of the
agape—eros problematic means that I have little to say here about her so-called
'essentialist’ account of gender, in its opposition to constructionist
accounts. According to Margaret Whitford, interpretation of Irigaray has long
been hindered by 'the deadlock produced by the terms of the essentialist/
antiessentialist debate’; in opposition to this, 'the multiplicity for which
she is celebrated should be a prescription for the reader as well’ ('Reading
Irigaray in the Nineties’, in C. Burke, N. Schor, M. Whitford (eds.), Engaging
with Irigaray, New York: Columbia University Press, 1994, 15—33, 15—16).
However, Irigaray’s advocacy of a feminism of difference, in opposition to a
feminism of equality, is related to the essentialist—constructionist
distinction and is one of a number of points at which her work diverges from
most recent north American feminist theology: see her critique of Elisabeth
Schussler Fiorenza’s In Memory of Her, 'Equal to Whom?’, ET in differences
1 (1988), 59—76. Another such divergence may be seen in Irigaray’s insistence
that in their difference man and woman belong together: see her sharply
critical comments on a purely 'between-women sociality’ in i love to you:
Sketch of a Possible Felicity in History (1992), ET London and New York:
Routledge, 1996, 1 — 6.
2 Works cited in the main text of this
chapter are as follows: An Ethics of Sexual Difference (1984), ET
London: Athlone Press, 1993; This Sex which is Not One (1977), ET New
York: Cornell University Press, 1985; Marine Lover of Friedrich Nietzsche
(1980), ET New York: Columbia University Press, 1991; 'Women-mothers: the
silent substratum of the social order’ (1981), ET in The Irigaray Reader,
ed. Margaret Whitford, Oxford: Blackwell: 1991, 47—52; Thinking the
Difference: For a Peaceful Revolution (1989), London: Athlone Press, 1994; je,
tu, nous: Toward a Culture of Difference (1990), ET London and New York:
Routledge, 1993.
Is
Heidegger right when he pronounces that ‘each age has one issue to think
through’, and adds, for still greater emphasis: ‘and one only’? On that view,
which is also Irigaray’s, it is ‘an age’ that thinks and speaks in the person
of the philosopher. At a particular moment in its unfolding, Spirit or Geist
thinks itself, and at this moment — our moment — it must think itself
not in its dialectical identity with itself but in the original, undialectical,
irreducible difference that lies concealed behind every such claim to
identity. Without detriment to its divinity, Spirit is the human spirit: it was
the philosophical task of an earlier age to establish this identity. Building
on this achievement, our age is called to recognize in ‘the human spirit’ itself
a secondary abstraction from the original fact that ‘spirit’ is always qualihed
as male or female. Male and female are not secondary derivatives of spirit but
its primary embodiments, and spirit is therefore twofold. The notion of a
unitary spirit that embraces difference is (perhaps) the product of a
Judaeo-Christian monotheistic prejudice; the apparent ‘naturalness’ of this
monotheism in the development of human thought may be nothing other than the
‘naturalness’ of patriarchy, a sign of its success in banishing the old gods
and goddesses and disguising the limited, male perspective of which it is the
projection. The task of a postChristian, post-monotheistic age, ‘after the
death of God’, is to think through the twofoldness that has so long been
concealed. If this twofoldness is the single issue of ‘our’ age, then — insofar
as the possessive pronoun includes both women and men — the difference that is
‘our’ allotted subject matter will require a differential treatment. Woman and
man will think through this difference from opposite sides of the boundary that
divides them, and their thinking will never simply coincide. Yet it is ‘one
issue, and one only’ that is given to them to think through, on behalf of the
‘age’ for which they speak. A unitary Geist continues to hover above the
articulation of‘sexual difference’, ensuring that the dialogical form issues in
a monological content.
‘Our
age’ articulates itself through its art and literature, but above all through
its philosophy; only in philosophy is the issue imposed on us adequately
‘thought through’. There is no place here for theology. The theme of
theology is theos, ‘God’, and our age knows itself to be an age ‘after
the death of God’. Like Heidegger and Nietzsche, Irigaray sees in the death of God
the necessary darkness that precedes the dawning of a new day in which the gods
are reborn. Philosophy too speaks of theos — but not in such a way as to
share a subject matter with theology. The death of God is the death of the Christian
God; and yet this God remains the subject matter of theology. Here, in deHance
of ‘our age’, this God is acknowledged still as ‘the living God’. Our age
cannot permit theology to play any part in its selfarticulation, for theology
is guilty of a great and fundamental anachronism, the sin against the
age itself — however skilfully it contrives to mimic contemporaneity. The time
for rational discourse (logos) about this theos has long since passed;
but the time of the ‘wisdom’ (sophia) beloved by philosophy is always
present. In the face of this exclusion order, theology can only appeal to the
fact that, where the theme of ‘sexual difference’ has been announced, a
dialogue between a ‘masculine’ logos and a ‘feminine’ sophia
might be a more appropriate expression of this theme than a philosophical
monologue. Whether or not ‘our age’ speaks in this dialogue is perhaps (pace
Heidegger) not very important.
Setting aside the
mythology of the age, its single issue and its philosophical mouthpiece, we
acknowledge that ‘sexual difference’ is indeed an important contemporary
issue. But what is this ‘sexual difference’? The phrase is ambiguous. ‘Sexual
difference’ is that difference that pertains to sex. But sex is twofold: sex is
gender, and it is sexual intercourse. Sexual difference is either the
difference that pertains to sexual intercourse or the difference that pertains
to gender; it takes either a narrower or a broader form. In the Hrst case, the
man and woman whose sexual difference is to be investigated are naked together,
in preparation for the sexual act. Their difference is displayed in the
difference of their genital organs, normally concealed but here revealed; the
concern will be to establish that the ‘difference’ in question is not that of
an inversion, in which one becomes — in Irigaray’s terms — the ‘container’ or
‘envelope’ for the other, but a genuine heterogeneity or otherness which must
be respected if the act is to be ethical. In the second case — ‘sexual
difference’ as gender difference — the man and woman (now clothed) are observed
as they act and speak in the course of their ‘everyday life’. Although they are
clothed (perhaps very similarly), it cannot be said that their ‘sexual
difference’ is concealed here and is uncovered only in their physical
nakedness. Sexual difference is nowhere concealed and everywhere manifest;
and, in this broad sense, sexual difference is one of the major issues of our
age because, although ubiquitous and fundamental, it has until now rarely
received the attention that it merits.
For Irigaray,
‘sexual difference’ embraces both gender difference in general and respect for
otherness within the sexual act in particular. It is assumed that the sexual
act is located at the centre of the relations between the sexes. In this
act, everything that occurs between man and woman is gathered together and
brought to light with a peculiar clarity and intensity; at this point, the
fundamental quality of the entire relationship is disclosed. The sexual act has
a representative function in relation to the other acts and speech-acts in
which man and woman engage with one another. For Irigaray, the key to gender
difference — in all its ramifications — lies in ethical sex. Sex (sexual
intercourse) is the telos towards which the male—female relationship naturally
gravitates, and if all is well here — if otherness is respected — then all will
be well on the way that leads to it and from it. Since to be human is always to
be human as male or female, sex as the key to the male—female relationship is
also the key to our humanity. It is therefore in the act of sexual union and
differentiation that we are most human and most ourselves as male or female: to
eros is assigned a virtually unqualified dominion over human existence. Granted
the fact of that dominion, the issue for our age is how this can be truly an ethical
dominion.
Within the dominion
of eros sex is compulsory, and this law creates great difficulties for Irigaray
as a reader of the gospels. The women who encounter Christ do so merely as
virgins or repentant sinners: ‘Are they nothing but ears? With just a bit of
mouth, eyes, and as much hand and leg as is needed to reach out and follow
after Him. They seek Him, not He them. If He does occasionally take notice of
them, it is out of his in®nite benevolence, neither needed nor earned. Sex is
virtually absent from their meetings, except for a few confessions or avowals
of morbid symptoms. He listens, but does not marry/ make merry with women, for
already he is bound to his heavenly Father’ (Marine Lover, 165—6). ‘Was
he like that? Or has tradition made him like that? The place of his loves is
rendered as virgin, or childlike, or adolescent. Must the Christic redemption
mean that the advent of the divine has never taken place in the incarnation of
a loving relation with the other? Must this messenger of life neglect or refuse
the most elementary realities? Must he be a timid or morbid adolescent, too
paralyzed to realize his desires, always attentive to his Father’s edicts,
executing the Father’s wishes even to the point of accepting the passion and
the Father’s desertion as the price of such ®delity . . . ? Who interpreted him
in this way? Who abominated the body so much that he glori®ed the son of man
for being abstinent, castrated?’ (177). The Father is the deity who in his
hatred for life forbids one passion — ‘you shall not desire’ — and commands
another, in which the flesh of his own son is torn apart.
Outside
the dominion of eros and the law of compulsory sex, one might read the gospels
differently. Jesus, as rendered in the gospel narratives, might serve to expose
the contemporary mythology which claims that humanity without sex (sexual
intercourse) is defective, that we become fully human only in and through sex,
that it is sex alone that establishes us as male or female, and that agape
without eros is an expression of hatred of life and the body. On the other
hand, if this mythology is held to be true, one might take up Irigaray’s
suggestion (‘has tradition made him like that?’) and postulate a sexually
active Jesus (heterosexual or homosexual, according to taste) that tradition
has sought to conceal. One might follow the lead of another writer, who reports
that ‘particularly in recent years there has been a passionate discussion of
the question whether Jesus had intimate relationships with Mary Magdalene’.
There is, after all, biblical evidence for this: in their Johannine
post-resurrection encounter, ‘there seems to be a delight, a happiness, an
eroticism which transcend the teacher-pupil relationship’.[l] From a standpoint such as this, a Jesus portrayed
as neither heterosexual nor homosexual, who commends those who castrate
themselves for the sake of the kingdom of heaven, cannot be the real
Jesus because he cannot truly ‘love’: the evangelists’ apparent omission of
sexuality from their rendering of Jesus’ varied relations to others is a skandalon
to contemporary piety. They appear to have believed that Jesus’ ‘sexuality’ was
as unimportant to his identity as the Christ as his physical appearance —
about which they are also silent.
'Sexual
difference would constitute the horizon of worlds more fecund than any known to
date ± at least in the West ± and without reducing fecundity to the
reproduction of bodies and flesh. For loving partners this would be a fecundity
of birth and regeneration, but also the production of a new age of thought,
art, poetry, and language: the creation of a new poetics'. (Ethics, 5)
‘Sexual
difference’ is the difference presupposed in and established by the sexual act
when it is performed ethically, in a manner respectful of the other. The sexual
act may or may not lie at the centre of the relationship of man and woman, that
whole manifold relationship may or may not gravitate towards it; but the
ethical significance of the sexual act is clear even if its precise scope
remains undetermined. It is significant that, among the various relationships
derived from the twofoldness of human nature, there is this ‘sexual’
relationship — not simply a relationship in which, contingently, sexual acts
occur, but a relationship constituted by this occurrence although not
reducible to it. Can it be said that the sexual act lies at the centre of this
form of the relationship of man and woman, that in this act they are most
fully themselves at least in their relation to this particular other? Is this
act truly a ‘consummation’, an act that perfects, completes and fulfils,
spreading like a canopy over the entire relationship? ‘This locus of my
concentration and of his opening out without futile dispersion constitutes a
possible habitation. Turning back on itself and protecting me until the next
encounter. A kind of house that shelters without enclosing me, untying and
tying me to the other, as one who helps me build and inhabit. Discharging me
from a deadly fusion and uniting me through an acknowledgment of who is capable
of building this place. My pleasure being, in a way, the material, one of the
materials. Architects are needed. Architects of beauty who fashion jouissance ±
a very subtle material' (Ethics, 214). The dwelling-place is formed just
here, on the site of the encounters that constitute the ‘sexual relationship',
because there occurs here, uniquely, a ‘communion in the secret depths of the
sensible realm' (211). (But might there not be many possibilities of
such a communion? Does the sexual relationship hold a monopoly over the secret
depths? Is the sexual act pure depth without banality or irony, a sacred rite
performed in a temple? Does it establish itself as a dwelling-place ex
nihilo, or does it find its natural habitat within an existing, material
dwelling-place: a home, a place of settled co-habitation? Does this
idealism of the flesh lack a material substructure?)[li]
The sexual act
establishes sexual difference; it is not to be described simply as ‘sexual
union', for union means oneness and in the sexual act there are two as well as
one. It is as an act of two that it is ‘fecund' and fruitful. ‘For loving
partners this would be a fecundity of birth and regeneration . . . ', and this
fecundity is not to be reduced ‘to the reproduction of bodies and flesh'. Each
individually, and the two together, give birth to one another in and through
the sexual act; in the act itself the command to be fruitful and multiply is already
fulfilled. The act is complete in itself, it is consummation and perfection. It
is an act of two not of one, but also not of three. It does not open out
towards a third, an other who is as yet unknown and merely potential. The
future onto which it opens out is its own future, the future in which the
sexual encounter of two ‘loving partners’ will again be re-enacted as the
architects resume their delicate labours. The fruitfulness of the encounter is
not to be ‘reduced’ to ‘reproduction’, but there is no corresponding warning against
reducing this fruitfulness to two, to the exclusion of the potential third. Is
the exclusion or marginalizing of the potential third (a merely biological
fruitfulness) a necessary condition of the true, spiritual fruitfulness?
Granted that the two must face one another and not look away to the potential
third, must the third be excluded from the communion of this mutual look? (That
is not the case within the doctrine of the Trinity.) If so, the sexual act in
its purest and most transparent form may require an act of exclusion, an
act dependent no longer upon nature but upon technology. By one technique or
another, male semen and female ovum must be kept apart, lest there should occur
a ‘deadly fusion’ and the loss of their twofoldness. Where the fusion is
allowed to occur this is an epiphenomenon of the act itself, in which the
creation of sexual difference is already fruitful in and of itself. The
potential third party has no part to play in the sexual relationship of these
‘loving partners’. They have eyes only for each other. Erotic idealism
envisages ‘a new age of thought, art, poetry, and language’, but it cannot
encompass the flesh of the child.
A child will turn
the ‘loving partners’ into a mother and a father, bound to one another anew, in
and through the child. The potential third party will irrevocably change
the loving partners; and according to Irigaray, he or she will thereby endanger
them. The child is a threat to their spiritual fecundity.
In the breakthrough
from sex into conception, pregnancy and birth, one of the loving partners is
transformed into a mother. The ordeal of childbirth is an initiation into
motherhood, and this is all too easily misunderstood as a transition into
‘full’ womanhood. Imperceptibly and without theoretical reflection, ‘woman’
comes to mean ‘mother’. ‘Most of the time women only make contact with each
other in the context of discussions concerning their children . . . But is this
definition, originally a male one, suitable for us? Or should we think about a
different female identity, in which the sufferings and joys of motherhood are
no longer the criteria for identification?' (je, tu, nous, 102, 103).
The motherhood of the one partner turns the other into a father, and this
transition too may be regressive in tendency. The loving partner may become a
patriarch. If, for example, the potential mother freely chooses to terminate
her pregnancy, her male partner may suddenly announce himself a devotee of the
cult of ‘the precious paternal seed', determined that ‘the mother-mistress can
and must suffer, or even die ... in order to honour those chromosomes of the
male race, that priceless logos spermatikos" (Marine Lover, 170).
In the transition to parenthood there is an acute danger of forgetting that ‘be
fruitful and multiply' does not ‘simply mean “make children'' for the Father,
but rather, create oneself and grow in the grace of fleshly fulfilment’ (170).
To create oneself, and not ‘simply' to make a child: in ethical sex one
excludes the potential third party, together with the threat to personal
integrity that it entails. In this way one practises safe sex.
Parenthood poses yet
another danger to the fecundity of sexual difference: the child displaces the
sexual act from the centre of the partners' relationship. There is perhaps a
grain of truth in Freud's largely false claim that for the mother the child
serves as a substitute for the penis she has always envied. But this claim
needs to be rewritten: for both parents, the child recentres a previously
erotically focused relationship around itself. The child displaces eros from
the centre of the relationship. The relationship is not reducible to
the child, any more than it was previously reducible to eros, but if it can be
said to have a ‘centre’ at all the child stands somewhere near that centre.
Eros does not disappear when displaced by the child, but the sexual act will
henceforth be the sexual act not simply of ‘loving partners' but of parents. If
the fecundity of eros is dependent on there being neither one nor three but
two, then eros will never again be fecund. Eros is therefore the mortal enemy
of the child. As in the Symposium (an older classic of erotic idealism),
eros prefers a spiritual progeny to a fleshly one. Is an idealism that can
speak disparagingly of ‘the reproduction of bodies and flesh', as though this
were a matter of little consequence, really a credible advocate of the human
body, male and female? In its insistent celebration of the flesh, is there a
silent drift towards an ambivalence, even a hostility, towards the flesh: the
flesh of the child, maternal flesh, paternal flesh?5
There may indeed be
personal loss as well as gain in parenthood, and especially in motherhood. A
tacit identification of womanhood and motherhood is indeed oppressive and destructive.
But what Irigaray gains in rejecting the law of compulsory motherhood she loses
by insisting on the law of compulsory sex. Her attack on the Jesus of the
gospels for flouting this law is an attack on everyone else, male or female,
who rejects the dominion of eros. Jesus, we recall, ‘neglects or refuses the
most elementary realities’ in his practice of sexual abstinence; he is ‘a timid
or morbid adolescent, too paralyzed to realize his desires’. Who was it that
‘abominated the body so much’ that he presented us with this pathetic,
castrated ®gure? Here Irigaray speaks for a certain understanding of manhood,
in which sexual experience — preferably extra-marital — is an initiation rite
that establishes one as a ‘real man’. Despite her critique of the concept of
‘equality’, this understanding of manhood is extended to womanhood in strictly
egalitarian fashion. One can be a woman without motherhood, but can one be a
real woman without sex? The women around Jesus are themselves implicated in his
unfortunate sexual abstinence. ‘Are they nothing but ears? With just a bit of
mouth, eyes, and as much hand and leg as is needed to reach out and follow
after Him.’ Do they not possess the complete faces, arms, legs, breasts, and,
in a word, bodies that would enable them to become his ‘loving partners’
rather than his servile ‘followers’? Irigaray is in agreement with this man and
these women when she insists that one can be woman or man without being mother
or father. But she does not even notice this agreement. What she does notice in
the gospels is the claim that one can be
5 Irigaray’s constant emphasis on the
importance of the mother—daughter relationship might lead one to qualify this
judgment (see for example 'The Bodily Encounter with the Mother’ [1981], in The
Irigaray Reader, 34—46). But her reflections on the 'genealogy of women’
are concerned with the daughter’s re-establishing the broken link with the
mother, as an instance of the need for a genuine intersubjectivity among women.
Even here, there is little reflection on the role of the mother as a mother.
man
or woman without sex. How unethical! What a denial of the body! 'Is not the
body more than clothing?' (Matt. 6.25). But the body is not more than sex. Sex
is the secret source of all its fecundity. Without sex it withers and dies.
UNNATURAL LAW
'If
traditionally, and as a mother, woman represents place for man, such a limit
means that she becomes a thing, with some possibility of change from one
historical period to another. She finds herself delineated as a thing.
Moreover, the maternal-feminine also serves as an envelope, a container,
the starting point from which man limits his things . . . But, because he
fails to leave her a subjective life, and to be on occasion her place and her
thing in an intersubjective dynamic, man remains within a master± slave
dialectic. The slave, ultimately, of a God on whom he bestows the
characteristics of an absolute master. Secretly or obscurely, a slave to the
power of the maternal-feminine which he diminishes or destroys. The
maternal-feminine remains the place separated from “its” own place, deprived
of “its” place. She is or ceaselessly becomes the place of the other who cannot
separate himself from it. Without her knowing or willing it, she is then
threatening because of what she lacks: a “proper” place'. (Ethics, 10—11)
Whether
or not human life is subjected to the unqualihed dominion of eros, it remains
the case that an ethic of the sexual act is needed - an ethic that goes beyond
the question of the dramatis personae: who is to perform it, and with
whom. In the sexual act one does not fall out of the ethical world into a
primal, pre-ethical relation. But that is what happens when male desire
construes woman as place but allows her no place of her own. She is place for
him, but he is not place for her. She offers him a place where he is again
enclosed and enveloped, a return to the original home in the womb and to the
bliss of the maternal embrace. In the Freudian narrative, the original Oedipal
ban on the maternal embrace is only temporary: the fulhlment of desire is to be
deferred until the boy becomes a man and the time is ripe for the movement of
return. But the temporary Oedipal ban is the work of the father — a point that
is emphasized especially in Lacan’s version of the Freudian narrative.6 It
is a prohibition imposed by the father on the son, and it is also a promise
that the son will one day enjoy the father’s access to the mother, or her
substitute. The prohibition and the promise are exclusively the affair of
father and son, they occur within an all-male relationship. The maternal object
of the prohibition and the promise is construed as place — a particular
place, home. In the Oedipal situation, two males negotiate a new
relation to this place, and the outcome is that the younger of the two leaves
home, in order to ®nd it again by way of a detour. Home is passive; it does not
move, and it does not itself initiate speech or action; it can hardly be said
even to wait, it is simply there. When one leaves it, it closes
up behind one and keeps itself in reserve so as to be intact for the moment
when it receives one back. But access to it is the affair of fathers and sons.
It is therefore not a person but a ‘thing’, infinitely precious because it
marks one’s place in the world by holding open the possibility of a return to
the arche, the first home that relieves one of the fate of an eternal
rootlessness and wandering. In sexual union, nostalgia is not compelled to
remain wistfully outside, looking in through the window, but is miraculously
reunited with the beloved object. It retains something of the bittersweet
quality derived from the original ban, but only so that the pain may be taken
up and transformed into the bliss of comfort. Father and son negotiate
together about their deepest needs.
How is it that
(according to Irigaray) woman has been changed into a place lacking a place of
its own? Like man, she too has experienced the loss of the original maternal
home. But here there has been no paternal prohibition; the loss occurs by way
of her own disillusion with the mother. According to Freud, the daughter
becomes disillusioned with a mother who had previously represented plenitude
and abundance, the ful®lment
6 As Juliet Mitchell shows, Lacan argues
— in opposition to object-relations theory — that 'the relation of mother to
child cannot be viewed outside the structure established by the position of the
father . . . There can be nothing human that pre-exists or exists
outside the law represented by the father’ ('Introduction I’, in J. Mitchell
and J. Rose, Feminine Sexuality: Jacques Lacan and the Ecole Freudienne,
Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1982, 23). of every desire, because she
discovers a lack, a hole, at the very centre of this supposed plenitude. Unlike
the father and the brother, the mother lacks a penis. So too does the daughter;
and the mother is quite unable to give her one. The illusion of plenitude is
dispelled, and the daughter's turn away from the mother towards the father is
undertaken of her own volition and not in reluctant obedience to an alien
authority. This turn does not mark the end of the Oedipal situation but the
beginning. The father is now the promise of plenitude: he will bestow the
longed-for penis, or rather, its equivalent, the child. This Oedipal dependence
is perhaps never overcome, and there is a smooth transition when in marriage
the woman is transferred from the custody of one male to that of another. If
the child she now bears possesses the penis she lacks, then her joy will be
complete: for it con®rms her in the role she has adopted in relation to males
(father, brothers, husband, son . . . ), which is to be their dwelling-place ±
not to have a place but to be a place. Her satisfaction lies in
their satisfaction. Thus she ®nally succeeds in occupying the space marked out
for her by her own mother, whom she has forgotten. There is no genealogical
connection with the mother to correspond to the genealogies of fathers and
sons, and there is no going back on the decision ± which was her own choice ±
to leave the original maternal home. It is her vocation not to return
home but to be home.
Within this account
of the genesis of masculine and feminine identity, the feminine exists only as
the inverted, negative image of the masculine. What is true of the part is true
of the whole: woman is ‘a hole-envelope that serves to sheathe and
massage the penis in intercourse: a non-sex, or a masculine organ turned back
upon itself, self-embracing’ (This Sex which is not one, 23). The hole
is the whole: woman is the original home, the arche, but this is a place
of absence and emptiness, an abyss into which one (the male ‘one’) falls.
Woman is the blissful dream of the return to the ®rst home, but she is also a
chaotic void. And she is all this because this is what a ‘primal male
sexuality’ has made of her: for ‘limiting oneself to just one of the poles of
sexual difference amounts to limiting oneself to the chaos of a primitive
desire that preceded any human incarnation . . . Urged by eros, man immerses himself
in chaos because he refuses to make love with an other, to be two
making love, to experience sexual attraction with tenderness and respect . . .
This notion of love has led women to forget themselves, to submit childishly or
slavishly to male sexuality, and to console themselves, through motherhood, for
their fall and exile from themselves' (Thinking the Difference, 97, 99).
The sexual relation is understood as a pre-ethical relation, and its
premise is the fall or exile in which woman is per manently separated from her
own ®rst home in order that she should herself be home to another.
The Freudian story
of an asymmetrical masculine and feminine becoming ends happily with the male
return to the original maternal home and the female acquisition of the longed-for
penis or child. How can it be said that woman is ‘trapped in the role of she
who satis®es need but has no access to desire' (‘Women-mothers', 51) when she
is herself so abundantly satis- ®ed in satisfying the desire of the male other?
What more does she want than what she already has? (A male suspicion: is she
insatiable?) According to Irigaray, she is not satis®ed because the desire that
has been satis®ed - the desire that takes up residence in her body and ®lls up
her lack — is not in fact her desire but another's desire that has long
since taken hold of her and reshaped her in its own image, the image of the
phallus. So artfully was this done that the alien and alienating desire looks
exactly as if it were truly her own. What could be more natural than that, on
discovering the value of the phallus, woman should long to possess it for
herself and turn away from one who merely mirrors her own lack? Where is the
opening here through which an alien desire could enter, so as to pass itself
off as her own? But the value of the phallus is not a natural value. The male
organ becomes the desired, envied phallus because it has been invested
with value by a social order which regards it as a passport to privileges from
which those who lack it are excluded.7 This
inflationary investment in the phallus turns it into the ideal commodity — so
seductive in its appeal to its consumers, so successfully marketed, that everyone
desires it.
7 'Freud gave the moment when boy and
girl child saw that they were different the status of a trauma in which the
girl is seen to be lacking . . . But something can only Those who possess it are
fearful only of losing it, those who lack it long to acquire it. The marketing
strategy is to make the desirability of this object appear inevitable, the
natural outcome of an inherent value. Like all advertising, it seduces by
making it dif®cult or impossible to interrogate the desire to which it appeals.
How could one do anything other than to de®ne oneself by one's possession or
lack of such an in®nitely desirable object? One already ®nds oneself de®ned as
such. Mother and daughter will be united only negatively, in the desire for
that which they both lack. The original positive relationship is permanently
erased. There is no detour and no return home.
The Freudian story
is retold by Irigaray as the true story of the genesis of patriarchy, founded
as it is upon this act of erasure. The story is historically true ± it
describes what happens ± but philosophically false, in assuming that what happens
happens naturally and had to happen.8 According
to Aristotle, ‘poetry is more philosophical and more worthy of serious
attention than history; for while poetry is concerned with universal truths,
history treats of particular facts' (Poetics, 9).9 The
Freudian history truthfully describes the particular facts of which it treats,
but it is false insofar as it wishes also to be poetry, a rendering of what is
universally and necessarily the case. A constantly re-enacted history that is
neither universal nor necessary must be replaced by a new history in which the
be seen to be missing
according to a pre-existing hierarchy of values' (Jacqueline Rose,
'Introduction II', Feminine Sexuality, 42).
8 'Does it go without saying that the
little girl renounces her first object cathexes, the precociously cathected
erogenous zones, in order to complete the itinerary that will enable her to
satisfy man's lasting desire to make love with his mother, or an appropriate
substitute? Why should a woman have to leave — and ''hate'' ... — her own
mother, leave her own house, abandon her own family, renounce the name of her
own mother and father, in order to take man's genealogical desires upon herself
?' (This Sex which is Not One, 65). Freud 'is describing an actual state
of affairs', when he de®nes the feminine 'as the necessary complement to the
operation of male sexuality, and, more often, as a negative image that provides
male sexuality with an unfailingly phallic self-representation' (70). This
actual state of affairs is the product of history, not nature; but it is
disguised as the natural state of affairs where anatomy is seen as 'an
irrefutable criterion of truth' (71). Women 'are deprived of the worth of their
sex. The important thing, of course, is that no one should know who has
deprived them, or why, and that ''nature'' be held accountable' (71).
9 Translation from Aristotle, Horace,
Longinus: Classical Literary Criticism, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1965.
mother-daughter
relationship remains intact and female subjectivity is thereby assured: a
subjectivity that is then taken forward into the (hetero)sexual relation so as
to ensure its creativity. An old era, in which sexual difference was subsumed
into the project of male self-dehnition, would then be succeeded by a new era
in which the twofoldness of human nature comes to full symbolic expression.
Irigaray’s
account of the loss of sexual difference may be compared to the transition from
the male/female distinction of creation to the male hegemony established in the
fall. ‘Your desire shall be for your husband, and he shall rule over you’ (Gen.
3.16).[lii] After eating the forbidden fruit, Adam and Eve
conceal their genitals as a sign of the shame of a new, disordered sexual
desire. According to Augustine, the involuntary erection of the penis is the
outward and visible sign of this desire. But it is also the sign of the desire (teshuqah)
of the woman for her husband: it signihes his desire for her, but it also
signihes her responsive desire for him. Why should her desire be signihed by
that which she herself lacks? How has sexual difference become an order in
which one is characterized by possession, the other by lack, so that the
twofoldness of human being is reduced to the polarity of plus and minus? Within
an order in which ‘your desire shall be for your husband and he shall rule over
you’, it is the man who possesses the signiher of desire: of his desire,
but also of her desire as one who lacks but who desires to incorporate
the signiher of her desire within her own body, even at the cost of subjection
to the dominance of the possessor. May she not subject herself to the one who
hlls her lack with his plenitude? May he not assume authority over the one
whose lack is so clearly intended by nature as the place at which his needs are
satished? As the phallus, the penis is now invested with a new role that causes
it to stand out from the other bodily members. It will of course perform the
reproductive function for which it was created. (‘Adam knew Eve his wife, and
she conceived . . . ’ (Gen. 4.1).) But it will also incarnate an order of
dominance and subjection that is, apparently, desired by both parties. This is
not simply an order imposed on the weak by the strong. ‘Your desire will be for
your husband’: those who lack will willingly subject themselves to those who
possess, so as to gain a share in their possession in the union of flesh.
Upheld by the desire of both parties, the rule of the phallus will be
indistinguishable from the order of nature.
In which case Freud
is perhaps right and Irigaray wrong? Perhaps human existence as male and female
is human existence plus and minus? If, according to the Genesis text,
human existence becomes this existence plus and minus (although ‘from
the beginning it was not so’), might this not be understood as an inevitable,
necessary process in which the ungendered innocence of an infancy in which one
knows nothing of good and evil is succeeded by the order of desire as naturally
as night follows day? The (so-called) ‘fall’ is perhaps a pictorial rendering
of the dawning of sexual self-consciousness, as the concealment of the genitals
indicates, and the asymmetrical desire signified by the phallus would then be
nothing other than the reverse side of this concealment, a phenomenon as
natural as the child’s discovery of itself as male or female, as possessing or
not-possessing. If the Genesis story is truly a story of human genesis, then
what is portrayed here is surely a natural development, an initiation into the
rule of the phallus as the law of nature? What scope is there here for any
other law?[liii]
But in the garden
Adam and Eve are not infants. They are created as man and woman; and the rule
of the phallus is not the telos of a natural development but an accident
that befalls their manhood and womanhood as the result of their own contingent
action. Irigaray's assumption that the reign of the phallus is an unnatural
reign is therefore fundamentally right. The woman who desires her husband as
the plenitude that ®lls her lack has been overtaken by an alien desire that
does not belong to her created nature. The man who desires as one possessing
the signi®er of desire has been similarly overtaken. The created twofoldness of
human nature is not a human nature plus and minus: male and female alike are
‘created in the image of God’ (Gen. 1.27), and the original difference can
hardly have been that of a plenitude and a lack. Human nature plus and minus is
superimposed onto this original difference, as an expression of the
alienation of the creature from the creator. A tragic narrative that culminates
in the barring of access to the tree of life can hardly be the rendering of a
‘natural development’.
The phallus itself
acknowledges, unwillingly, that its reign is not original. As Augustine argues,
the physiological possibility of the erection of the penis is assumed in the
original command and vocation to be fruitful and multiply. Through the fall, a
voluntary bodily movement becomes an involuntary bodily occurrence that
generates such shame in the man and the woman that their immediate reaction is
to conceal the sites of ‘plenitude’ and ‘lack’. The signiher of desire, which
one possesses and the other lacks and which thereby establishes an order of
lordship and subjection, is the signiher of an alien desire which has
already subjected man himself to its own lordship. He possesses the signiher of
desire, but he does not control it. It controls him. He is not in full
possession of that which he possesses. The garments of hg-leaves are an attempt
to contain and conceal a desire so overwhelmingly powerful that it will
‘normally’ be aroused not just by voluntary sexual activity but by the mere
involuntary sight of the unclothed body of the other. The erection of the
signiher of desire is at the same time an occasion for shame that never escapes
the imperative of concealment. Only when carefully screened from public view
does it allow itself to be seen by its possessor and, perhaps, by his sexual
partner. This strange symbol of male dominance behaves almost like a furtive
nocturnal animal that can be glimpsed only occasionally and in passing. It can
assert its claim to dominance only by way of surrogates ± forms of male
selfdisplay which stand in for that which is unavoidably absent,
concealed behind screens far more effective than the original ®g-leaves;
surrogates that signify a supreme signi®er that is present only on the margins
of discourse and practice. These surrogates will be careful not to allow their
relation to the supreme signi®er to become too visible and obvious. They must
visibly signify only themselves, so as to have an alibi to hand if the issue of
a relation to the supreme signi®er is raised. Modes of dress and deportment,
displays of wealth and power, control of discourse, various forms of technological
mastery . . . Are these what they appear to be, and no more? Or are they signs
of the reign of the phallus? To interpret them as surrogates of the supreme
signi®er is, however, to subvert them and expose them to ridicule. If they are
expressions of the reign of the phallus, they are so only so long as that
relationship is kept secret. But what kind of a signi®er of male dominance is
it that can never openly appear but must always hide itself, even in its
surrogates? Why is it that the surrogates themselves must deny all knowledge
of their master and of their own role as his deputies? If this is the strategy
of a power that can penetrate everywhere only so long as it remains invisible, why
must the condition of universal penetration be this strict incognito? The
emperor may hide himself away to preserve the aura of divinity, but his
deputies do not feign ignorance of his very existence. Is the incognito more
plausibly understood as the product of shame, and thus as an admission
that the reign of the phallus is nonoriginal and contingent, a corruption of
the relation between man and woman given in creation? And, if the reign of the
phallus cannot be sustained but is ± like the house built on sand ± liable to
sudden collapse, might it be possible to divest the bodily organ of some of its
symbolic pretensions and to restore it to the male body as one member among
many? A ‘circumcision performed without hands’, a participation in ‘the circumcision
of Christ’ (Col. 2.11)? A non-being of male and female and a oneness in Christ
Jesus that is actually the fulfilment of the sexual difference given in
creation, and not its erasure (Gal. 3-28)?
If there
is any truth in this Pauline-Augustinian rewriting of Freud and Irigaray, the
ethics of sexual difference must be grounded in being itself. In identifying,
analysing and explaining the unethical or sub-ethical forms of the male-female
relation, one implicitly or explicitly appeals to a true ethical relation as
the ground both of critique and of hope. Only so can the naturalness of the
order of the phallus be shown to be unnatural.
THE DIVinE LIFE AND THE CREATURE
'What
we need is to discover how
two can be made which one day could become a one in that third which
is love . . . No more dissociation of love and eroticism. This very often
correlates with the division and hierarchy of parental functions. This way love
becomes a perpetual tragedy, a sad charity, or a greedy devotion (a form of
agape without eros, perhaps?)' (Ethics, 66-7)
No
dissociation of love and eroticism, no agape without eros; no assigning of eros
to man and agape to woman, no difference without union or union without
difference. If eros is a male prerogative, then woman will be the place where
that prerogative is exercised: difference will be dissolved into a oneness in
which the distinctive being of the second is lost. If agape is a female
prerogative, then man will be the object of a love that he cannot reciprocate:
he will become the place where this love is invested, and will himself be threatened
with the loss of his own distinctive being. The two are to become one in such a
way that they are two precisely in becoming one. If they establish their
twoness in their oneness, the oneness of their shared love can be understood as
a third, standing alongside their twoness rather than dissolving it, but also
ensuring that they are two not as pure individuals or units but in the oneness
of the relation with the other. The presence of the third indicates that
difference is not engulfed in an ultimate, undifferentiated oneness; for there
can be talk of a third only where there is not one alone but also two. Yet, in
doubling back on the two, the third also indicates that their difference is not
heterogeneity but is constituted by their oneness. The triune structure of the
relationship of man and woman is to be distinguished from a ‘monotheism’ in
which difference is dissolved and a ‘polytheism’ in which difference is
absolutized. Both monotheism and polytheism are attempts to escape the
trinitarian dialectic in which oneness and threeness are mutually constitutive
and therefore equally irreducible to the other. In establishing the difference
in the oneness and the oneness in the difference, the third is integral to the
relational structure. Three is two plus one, neither two alone nor one alone
but two together with their oneness. The oneness of two is more like an
addition to two than a subtraction. ‘There is neither male nor female, for you
are all one in Christ Jesus’ (Gal. 3.28): a subtraction, a dissolution of two
into one? But it is also said that ‘woman is not apart from man nor man from
woman, in the Lord’ (1 Cor. 11.11). In the Lord, in the oneness of being in
Christ Jesus, man is established as man and woman as woman; they are
established in their difference. But in their difference they are also
established as belonging together. Woman and man are not apart from one
another, as pure individuals or units, for they are what they are — woman and
man — only in relation to the other. For Irigaray, the love in which man and
woman are both two and one is the concrete expression of their being. In the
love that unites them and differentiates them, they find themselves. It is
within this trinitarian interrelatedness that we ‘discover how two can
be made which . . . become a one in that third which is love’.
Is there in all this
a vestigium trinitatis, a sign of the ultimacy of a triune relationality
in which difference is not dissolved into oneness but established by it? If the
love of man and woman is erotic love, is eros the closest human analogue to the
divine life? But the oneness of male and female in Christ Jesus is not the
oneness of erotic union as one flesh. The belonging-together of woman and man
is not confined to the sexual relationship, nor is that even its primary
expression. The veil is interposed in order to confine eros to his limits,
excluding him from the ekklesia, the place in which the
belonging-together of man and woman is disclosed, and differentiating him from
the agape which is the mode of that belonging-together. ‘A form of agape
without eros, perhaps?’ An infringement of the rule, ‘No more dissociation of
love and eroticism’? The ekklesia includes unmarried people whose
calling is not to become ‘one flesh’ in marriage but to the discipline of
celibacy, and — at least from one point of view — this can even be seen as the
higher of the two vocations:
The
unmarried man [ho agamos] is concerned about the affairs of the Lord,
how to please the Lord; but the married man [ho gamesas] is concerned
about worldly affairs [ta tou kosmou], how to please his wife, and his
interests are divided. And the unmarried woman [he gune he agamos] or
girl [parthenos] is concerned about the affairs of the Lord, how to be
holy in body and spirit; but the married woman [he gameesasa] is
concerned about worldly affairs, how to please her husband. (1 Cor. 7.32b—34)
According
to this Pauline teaching, the unmarried state is not to be seen as a negation,
a deprivation, a failure to achieve what must be achieved to be truly man or
woman, but a divine vocation. In living the single life one follows the example
of Paul (1 Cor. 7.7—8), who himself follows the example of Jesus (11.1). In
these single lives, the place of eros is marked by egkrateia,
‘self-control’ (7.9). But in these lives too it is the case that ‘woman is not
apart from man nor man from woman, in the Lord’ (11.10): for the primary
belonging-together of man and woman occurs not in sexual union or marriage but
in the agape that establishes the community as the body of Christ, without
obliterating the difference between its various ‘members’ (12.12—26). Within
the ekklesia there is indeed ‘a form of agape without eros’, in defiance
of the law that prohibits the ‘dissociation of love and eroticism’. (On what
authority is it asserted that man and woman become two and one primarily, or
even exclusively, in the sexual act? Must sexual experience be seen as a
compulsory rite of passage into ‘real’ manhood or womanhood, without which they
are deficient? Must this manhood and womanhood be sustained in being by an
ongoing ‘sex life’, within a single relationship or — preferably? — a plurality
of relationships? Must manhood and womanhood necessarily wither and die without
the nourishment of sex?) The belonging-together of man and woman in the ekklesia
is a sign of the primacy of agape over eros.
If the eros of man
and woman is seen as a vestigium trinitatis, and perhaps as a
participation in the trinitarian divine life, the concrete form of that divine
life will almost inevitably be undermined. The concrete form of the divine
life is the reciprocal love of the Father and the Son in the Holy Spirit. It is
in the descent of the Spirit in the form of a dove that Jesus knows himself to
be addressed as ‘my beloved Son’, and it is in that same Spirit that he
responds: ‘Abba, Father’. If heterosexual eros is elevated to the status of vestigium
trinitatis, then the absence both of the feminine and of eros itself within
the concrete form of the divine life will immediately seem problematic. The
father-son relationship is, ostensibly, all-male and non-erotic — and thus,
from the standpoint of Irigaray’s religious philosophy of eros, alienating and
offensive. From that perspective, it appears that ‘the perfection of love
between son and Father, with its completion in a Trinity’ makes the Christ-
symbol ‘eternally captive to the lure of a (male) Same’ (Marine Lover,
186). The hgure of the Christ is worth re-evaluating ‘only if he goes beyond
the Father—son relationship. If he announces — beyond Christianity? — that only
through difference can the incarnation unfold without murderous or suicidal
passion’ (188). As things stand, however, ‘the other has yet to enlighten him.
To tell him something. Even to appear to him in her irreducibility. . . And if,
to the whole of himself, he says “yes” and also asks her to say “yes” again,
did it ever occur to him to say “yes” to her? Did he ever open himself to that
other world?’ Can we create from the Christ-symbol ‘a marriage that has never
been consummated and that the spirit, in Mary, would renew?’ — a spirit that is
no longer ‘the product of the love between Father and son’ but rather ‘the
universe already made flesh or capable of becoming flesh, and remaining in
excess to the existing world’ (190). If heterosexual eros is image of and
participation in the divine life, then the concrete form of the
inner-trinitarian life will have to be radically reinterpreted. If we take the
way from eros into the divine life, the Father, the Son and the Holy Spirit
will be at best an irrelevance.
But if
the agape of the inner-trinitarian life is opened up to human participation in
the incarnation and through the Spirit, then the way from the human sphere into
the divine is preceded by and grounded in the prior way from the divine sphere
into the human. The point at which the divine way downwards and the human way
upwards intersect is the moment in which the one who descended from heaven
‘lifted up his eyes to heaven and said, Father, the hour has come; glorify thy Son
that the Son may glorify thee’ (Jn. 17.1). Does this represent an all-male
divine relationality that excludes the feminine, the apotheosis of patriarchy?
But the one addressed as ‘Father’ is not the oppressive heavenly patriarch of
contemporary imagining. ‘Abba’ is functionally equivalent to a proper name, and
the one so addressed is therefore a particular father who cannot be assimilated
to an abstract fatherhood-in-general. Fathers, and even Father-Gods, are not
necessarily all alike. If the one Jesus addresses as ‘Abba’ is diametrically
opposed to every other Father-God, exposing them as idolatrous projections,
this is not just another of patriarchy’s in-house conflicts. And, although eros
is indeed excluded from the inner-trinitarian life, being (like gender) a
purely creaturely reality, it is not the case that the relationship of Father
and Son is ‘all male’. Considered as an inner-divine relation, the absence of a
feminine other — a Mother, a Daughter — is an indication not of an apotheosis
of male gender but of its absence. Male and female are male and female in
relation to each other; where the female is absent, there is no male. (The
gendering of the Holy Spirit as female would therefore bestow a maleness on the
Father and the Son that was not previously there. It would also open up various
possibilities of heterosexual eros within the triune life.)12 While
the terms ‘father’ and ‘son’ normally denote male humans in a peculiarly
sharply defined and irreversible relationship to one another, they lose certain
of their normal concomitants — temporal separation, bodiliness, maleness — when
metaphori-
12 For these reasons, I no longer find
the use of feminine pronouns in connection with the Spirit to be appropriate
(compare Text, Church and World, 215—17). cally applied to the first and
second persons of the divine Trinity. This is no more an all-male relationship
than it is a temporal or bodily relationship.[liv]
The question of
maleness only arises when, in the incarnation, the inner-trinitarian agape is
extended into the human sphere in and through a particular man — and not a
woman. But the relation of Jesus to the heavenly Father is an inclusive relation.
In Christ there is neither Jew nor Greek, slave nor free, male nor female, in
the sense that no one is excluded from the koinonia of this relation.
That Jesus is ‘born of the virgin Mary’ is already an anticipation of this koinonia.
It is true of him as of all other males that ‘man is now born of woman’ (1 Cor.
11.12) and that the belonging-together of man and woman must initially take the
form of the relationship of mother and son. ‘Did it ever occur to him to say
“yes” to her?’ His birth was his ‘yes’ to Mary, who became his mother as he
became her son. His ‘yes’ to his mother is constitutive of his human existence.
To reject this form of the belonging-together of man and woman, to wish to
replace it with a relationship centred on sexual union, is indeed to go ‘beyond
Christianity’. Eros demands the movement ‘beyond Christianity’ because he
cannot endure the limit imposed on him by the divine-human agape.
In the koinonia
woman and man belong together not in eros but in this agape. But the koinonia
comprehends the whole of life — a life in which there is also marrying and
giving in marriage, in accordance with the will of the Creator. Marriage bears
witness to agape as a reciprocal love in which there is unreserved and
enduring commitment to the other; and where there is marriage within the koinonia
of the church, the basis of marriage within the divine agape is known and
acknowledged. The fact that man and woman belong together in Christ within the
‘one body’ is quite compatible with their belonging-together as ‘one flesh’,
within marriage. Agape does not need eros; there could be a church without
eros, but there could not be a church without agape. Agape marks the limit of
eros’s presence within the church. But agape is not opposed to eros. Agape
limits eros, but it also sanctifies it; that is, it sets it in the sphere of
the eternal divine commitment to humankind, of which marriage is the sacramentum
(Eph. 5.32). As the divine grace justifies the ungodly, so the divine agape
sanctifies eros. And we may expect to find traces of this divine action in the
belonging-together of man and woman inside and outside the church.
It is
this belonging-together of man and woman in agape, in their difference and
their oneness, their twoness and the third that is their oneness, that is the
true vestigium trinitatis - originating as it does in the
being-in-action of the triune God. Sanctified by agape, eros too may
participate in its trinitarian structure.
'Who
or what the other is, I never know. But the other who is forever unknowable is
the one who differs from me sexually. This feeling of surprise, astonishment,
and wonder in the face of the unknowable ought to be returned to its locus:
that of sexual difference . . . Sometimes a space for wonder is left to works
of art. But it is never found to reside in this locus: between man and
woman. Into this place came attraction, greed, possession, consummation,
disgust, and so on. But not that wonder which beholds what it sees always as if
for the®rst time, never taking hold of the other as its object. It does not try
to seize, possess, or reduce this object, but leaves it subjective, stillfree.'
(Ethics, 1 3)
Does
this speak of eros as a divinity who claims to mediate between the human and
divine spheres and to bestow a participation in the divine life manifested in
the face of the other? Or does it speak of eros as sanctified by the divine
agape - although perhaps unaware of this basis within God’s being and action?
If this eros sancti®ed by agape is a reality at all, it is the reality of man
and woman as such: the twofold human being created in the image and likeness of
God, male and female. It is not the reality merely of a Christian man and
Christian woman; for the new creation does not destroy the old, replacing it
with something qualitatively different, but fulfils the telos of the old
in the face of the disruption and confusion brought about by human sin. Even
where the basis of the eros of man and woman in the divine agape is
unacknowledged, even where eros is consequently distorted, this basis is real
and cannot be ineffectual. Irigaray’s supposedly ‘post-Christian’ ethics of sexual
difference questions and denies this reality in its quest for an alternative,
wholly future reality. But this reality is capable of making its presence felt
even in the midst of questions and denials; perhaps more so here than in bland
theological affirmations unmarked by any struggle with the temptation to
question and deny.
‘Who or what the
other is, I never know.’ This is the not- knowing not of indifference but of wonder
— ‘that wonder which beholds what it sees always as if for the ®rst time, never
taking hold of the other as its object’. Wonder is ‘a mourning for the self as
an autarchic entity’, it is ‘the advent or the event of the other’, ‘the
beginning of a new story’ (75). In the advent or event of the other, the other
is seen as if for the first time: the strangeness that evokes wonder is
therefore the strangeness of the familiar, the partial disclosure of that which
lies concealed behind the veil of the everyday; a disclosure not of divinity
but of the original goodness of the creature, and of the speci®c goodness of
the human creature whose free subjectivity corresponds to one’s own, across
the boundary of sexual difference. Without this correspondence human existence
would be solitary and ‘not good’ (Gen. 2.18); its goodness lies in the correspondence
disclosed in the advent of the other, of Eve to Adam and of Adam to Eve. Wonder
is evoked by the advent not of an alien other such as the animals brought to
Adam to name, but of an other who is other precisely in the correspondence of
reciprocal recognition across the boundary of difference. This advent is always
the divine gift, as Eve is gift to Adam and Adam to Eve, and wonder is
therefore always also gratitude - gratitude to being and, however
indirectly, to God as the ground of being. The advent of the other across the
boundary of sexual difference does not only occur in the context of
eros. But it may occur in that context. Eros is certainly not closed to
the advent of the
other
and the wonder that this evokes, and indeed it has its own particular mode of
openness to that advent. Where eros is closed to the other ± where it is
characterized merely by ‘attraction, greed, possession, consummation, disgust,
and so on’ ± this occurs in deHance of the openness to the other that is
originally proper to eros.
How may eros’s
distinctive mode of openness to the other be characterized? No adequate answer
to this question is possible, since to ‘wonder’ is precisely to be conscious of
the inadequacy of what can be said to what is felt. Experience is not always
reducible to language, any more than its possibility is always pre-given in
language; experience is always in excess of language. This excess is
especially clear in the case of erotic experience, which may even be said to resist
language. The sexual act requires speech if it is to be a reciprocal, communicative
act, human rather than inhuman, but it does not in itself require much
speech, nor does it require to be much spoken about. It is true that
discourse circulates incessantly around the sexual act, inHltrating even what
seem to be its most secret recesses for the sake of the pleasure of ‘speaking
openly’ about it. But the pleasure of speaking, hearing or reading of eros is
distinct from the pleasure of eros itself. The former pleasure is not a
preparation for the latter, or an enhancement of it; there is no necessary
relationship between the two, and it may be that any reducibility of eros to
speech indicates a drift away from its basis in agape. It seems that eros is
resistant to speech, whether in the form of conversation or of commentary. At
this point, words fail. Even a word such as ‘pleasure’, long associated with
the sexual act, is inadequate to eros: not simply because this word is lacking
in depth, but because it appears to assimilate an experience which is sui
generis to other experiences of pleasure, from which it differs totally.
The failure of words is not in itself a sign of a mystery beyond words, as
though words could only be concerned with the surface of life and not with its mysteries
and depths. Words may be lacking on the surface too, and they may on occasion
give profound articulation to the depths. Speechlessness may characterize
banality as well as mystery, and the resistance of eros to speech does not in
itself guarantee the presence even of a creaturely mysterium tremendum,
let alone a divine one. Yet this reticence is at least compatible with the
presence of a creaturely mysterium tremendum, with the 'feeling of
surprise, astonishment, and wonder in the face of the unknowable’ evoked by
'the advent or the event of the other’. The creaturely mystery that may be
encountered here — although normally crowded out by 'attraction, greed,
possession, consummation, disgust, and so on’ — is that of the original
goodness of the human creature, as male and female and always concretely as this
male and this female, unique in their specihc difference and
togetherness.[lv]
'So
as not to remain fixed on a rare object, it is appropriate to turn voluntarily
toward
several objects. So as not to be attached to one unique woman, is it
desirable to scatter oneself among several?' (Ethics, 79)
If in
the sexual act — as in other encounters between man and woman — one may
indirectly, fleetingly experience something of the original goodness of the
human creature, one is surely at liberty to maximize this experience? To
seek it wherever it may be found, beyond the exclusive commitment to one that
characterizes conventional marriage? The original goodness of the other, and of
oneself in union with the other, is unique to that particular other, male or
female, and to that particular relationship. It cannot be found elsewhere, and
if it is not found here it will be lost forever. If wonder 'sees always as if
for the first time’, if it marks 'the beginning of a new story’, why should one
not initiate a number of new stories? Is it mere prejudice and timidity that
can see in such ventures nothing more than 'adultery’ or 'promiscuity’?
This is the logic of
an eros without agape. The divine agape is an unreserved, eternal commitment to
the human creature, and therefore to the particular human creature; and
marriage is a divinely appointed analogue or sacramentum of the divine
agape. If, in eros, there has occurred 'the advent of the other’, this is not a
transitory event that is immediately overtaken by other events, but a sign
pointing to the unreserved, eternal commitment of the divine agape to the
particular human other. To turn from that other to a third party is to destroy
the sign by imposing a limitation on commitment and therefore on agape. To
change the object of commitment in accordance with inclination and opportunity,
drawn from one to another by the allure of the new, is precisely what agape cannot
do. It is only faithfulness to one that corresponds to the divine faithfulness;
the jealousy and anger evoked by the turning away of a husband or wife to a
third party are symptoms of the rupturing of this correspondence. In this
turning away, it is assumed that the former possibility of a 'wonder’ that 'sees
always as if for the first time’ is now exhausted, that it has degenerated into
irreconcilable conflict or routinized monotony. Yet the original goodness of
the human creature does not degenerate in this way. It is eternally af®rmed by
the divine agape, and to turn away from this disclosure in quest of another is
to show that the content of this disclosure has been forgotten or was never
properly grasped. The original goodness of the particular human creature is now
considered apart from the Creator, as contingent not on the eternal divine
judgment but on the successive, perhaps shifting judgments of its human
partner. The other to whom I am at present joined is good only insofar as I
continue to regard her as good. She is thereby deprived of the eternal place
accorded to her by the divine af®rmation, to which my commitment to her should
correspond, and her being is annexed and made dependent on my own. My own being
thereby falls out of its relation to the divine affirmation, as I set myself in
the place of the Creator as the ultimate judge of good and evil. I find,
perhaps, that what once seemed good now seems evil, and I therefore turn away
from it to seek the good elsewhere. But the good I appear to find will in no
way correspond to the original goodness of the human creature as eternally
affirmed by its Creator. I will find only an eros without agape: sin.
'The
consequences of the nonfulfillment of the sexual act remain, and there are
many. To take up only the most beautiful, as yet to be made manifest in the
realm of time and space, there are angels. These messengers who never remain
enclosed in a place, who are also never immobile. Between God, as the perfectly
immobile act, man, who is surrounded and enclosed by the world of his work, and
woman, whose task would be to take care of nature and procreation, angels would
circulate as mediators of that which has not yet happened, of what is still
going to happen, of what is on the horizon. Endlessly reopening the enclosure
of the universe, of universes, identities, the unfolding of actions, of history
. . . They are not unrelated to sex. There is of course Gabriel, the angel of
the annunciation. But other angels announce the consummation of marriage,
notably all the angels in the Apocalypse and many in the Old Testament. As if
the angel were a representation of a sexuality thathas never been incarnated.'
(Ethics, 15-16)
‘All’
the angels of the Apocalypse, ‘many’ in the Old Testament, announce the
consummation of a marriage and the incarnation of a new sexuality in which
sexual union gives birth to sexual difference, set now within a cosmic context.
‘The link uniting or reuniting masculine and feminine must be horizontal and
vertical, terrestrial and heavenly. . . [I]t must forge a covenant between the
divine and the mortal, such that the sexual encounter would be a festive
celebration . . . ’ (17). It is this future event that the angels announce — an
event beyond the Father and the Son. ‘The third era of the West might, at last,
be the era of the couple: of the Spirit and the Bride? After the coming
of the Father that is inscribed in the Old Testament, after the coming of the
Son in the New Testament, we would see the beginning of the era of the Spirit
and the Bride . . . The Spirit and the Bride invite beyond genealogical destiny
to the era of the wedding and the festival of the world' (148—9). Which apocalypse
is here paraphrased? In the canonical one, it is written: ‘The Spirit and the
Bride say, Come . . . And let the one who is thirsty come, let the one who
desires take the water of life without price' (Rev. 22.17). This water of life
flows ‘from the throne of God and of the Lamb through the middle of the street
of the city' (22.1—2). The Spirit and the Bride direct us to God and to the
Lamb as the source of living water; they do not proclaim a third age in which
God and the Lamb are superseded. The angels announce a future consummation —
but it is ‘the marriage supper of the Lamb' (19.19), and the Bride is ‘the wife
of the Lamb' (20.9). A new sexuality, or the new Jerusalem, the eternal
dwelling-place of the people of God in God and of God in his people? In the new
Jerusalem, the cube-shaped holy of holies built of gold and precious stones,
the promise is fulfilled and the dwelling of God is with humans: ‘He will dwell
with them, and they shall be his people, and God himself will be with them'
(21.3). Within this dwelling-place of God among humans and of humans in God,
this meeting of heaven and earth, is there a place for a new sexuality? Why
should this be excluded? Uncleanness and fornication are excluded from the
heavenly city (21.27, 22.15), but eros sanctified by agape is not uncleanness
or fornication. On the other hand, the Lamb's one hundred and forty four
thousand followers are described as ‘virgins' — male virgins, apparently, who
‘have not defiled themselves with women' (14.4). An obscure, one-sided allusion
to a time in which ‘they neither marry nor are given in marriage, but are like
angels in heaven' (Matt. 22.30)? A time in which eros is no more? Would it be
so terrible if it were eros — and not the Father or the Son — who was
superseded in the age of the resurrection of the flesh?
And yet, sexual
difference is preserved in the image of the Lamb and the Bride. The end of eros
is the end only of a sign, superseded by the reality of the fulfilled,
consummated divine— human covenant to which — when sanctified by agape — it
once pointed.
CHAPTER
SIX
After
many vicissitudes, Levin (Constantine Dmitrich Levin) and Kitty (Ekaterina Shcherbatskaya)
®nally arrive at the church for their wedding. Throughout Tolstoy's novel,
their developing relationship serves as the positive counterpart of Anna
Karenina's adulterous relationship with Count Vronsky, which offers her an
escape from a loveless marriage but ends with her suicide. The wedding is the
hinge on which the whole novel turns. Starting from the intense emotional
experiences of the couple at the centre of the event, the narrator moves
outwards into the concentric circles of relatives and friends and of interested
spectators of this ‘society wedding'. As the service proceeds, members of these
inner and outer circles comment on the unfolding drama like a Greek chorus.
All
Moscow was in the church - relatives, friends and acquaintances. During the
ceremony of plighting troth, in the brilliantly lit church, among the throng of
elegantly clad women and girls, and men in white ties, frock-coats or uniforms,
conversation in decorously low tones never flagged. It was mostly kept up by
the men, for the women were absorbed in watching every detail of the service,
which is so close to their hearts. (Anna Karenina, 480)1
Yet the
women have their say as well as the men. Like a roving microphone, the narrator
picks up snatches of conversation. ‘Why is Marie in lilac? It's almost as
unsuitable at a wedding as black.' ‘With her complexion it's her only
salvation. I wonder why they're having the wedding in the evening, like shoppeople?'
(480). The bridegroom's brother jokingly explains to
1 Quotations are taken from the
translation by Rosemary Edmonds, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1954. the
bride’s sister ‘that the custom of going away after the wedding was becoming
common because newly-married couples always felt slightly embarrassed’ (481).
But the most important question is: how will this marriage turn out? ‘Well,
let’s see which of them is the first to step on the carpet. I told Kitty to
remember’, remarks the unconventional Countess Nordston to the other of the
bride’s sisters. ‘It won’t make any difference’, she replies; ‘we all make
obedient wives — it runs in the family.’ ‘Well, I stepped on the carpet before
Vassily on purpose’ (481). The ‘carpet’ is where the couple stand for the
marriage ceremony itself, after the preliminary part of the service has been
completed. According to the old saying, ‘the one who steps first on the carpet
will be the head of the house’ (483). If the bride reaches the carpet first, by
luck or design, she will be the dominant partner in the marriage — unless, of
course, heredity and upbringing prove more effectual than the old tradition.
(‘We all make obedient wives — it runs in the family.’) On this occasion, bride
and bridegroom both forget the old tradition as they step together onto the
carpet, and are unaware of ‘the loud remarks and disputes that followed, some
maintaining that Levin was first and the others insisting that they had both
stepped on together’ (483).
In the outer circle
too, the issue of obedience is raised. ‘Is that her sister in the white satin?
Now listen how the deacon will roar: “Wife, obey thy husband’’’ (482). This
expectation is fulfilled when, at the reading of the Epistle, ‘the head-deacon
thunder[s] out the last verse, awaited with such impatience by the outside
public’ (483). The reference is presumably to the last verse of Ephesians
5.22—33 — a passage already alluded to in the preceding prayers, during which
bride and groom ‘were reminded that God created woman from Adam’s rib, and
“for this cause shall a man leave his father and mother, and cleave unto his
wife, and they twain shall be one flesh’’, and that “this is a great mystery’’’
(483). The conclusion of this passage is not quite, ‘Wife, obey your husband’,
but it is, ‘Let the wife see that she respects her husband’ — in the context of
a passage that has required her to submit to her husband’s headship. The
deacon’s fortissimo rendering of this text is evidently a personal foible, well
known to those who habitually attend wedding ceremonies in this fashionable
Moscow church. No doubt it is intended as a forceful reminder to the bride and
other wives present of a scriptural precept they often appear to overlook, but
it succeeds only in introducing a crudely dissonant note into the performance
of the solemn rites ± entertaining for uninvolved onlookers, although some of
those in the inner circle may perhaps wince at it. Does the church (in the
person of the head-deacon) really think that it can enforce its most offensive
precepts merely by shouting?
The issue of
obedience (the wife's obedience, or her lack of it) is raised both by scripture
(the Epistle) and by tradition (the carpet). It is, in one sense, still a ‘live
issue'; real tensions and sensitivities underlie the humour and the irony (‘it
runs in the family'). And yet in another sense it is irrelevant. Some maintained
that Levin was ®rst onto the carpet, others that they stepped onto it together:
they were so close that it was impossible to tell. If Levin is to be the head
of this particular house, his headship will in practice be almost
imperceptible. Indeed, ‘headship' and ‘subjection' - the terms used in the
Epistle - are simply inappropriate to the complex dynamics of this particular
relationship. Much of what is said during the service seems to be both
beautiful and true — so far as Levin and Kitty are aware of it through the haze
of joyful emotion that envelops them. But the two moments when the question of
obedience is raised pass them by, unnoticed. Where there is love, why should
there be talk of obedience? In spite of the deacon's best efforts, the Epistle
falls on deaf ears. Perhaps at another time and place its words were beautiful
and true, but they are so no longer. They are the empty shell of what may once
have been a living communicative act, preserved like a fossil in a museum when
the life has long since departed.
‘Can these bones
live?' What if one were to read this passage not fortissimo but sotto voce?
Emphasizing that the subjection required of the wife is not to a tyrant but to
a ‘head' who is himself enjoined to love as Christ loves the church; hinting
that this asymmetry may after all correspond to woman's own nature; indicating,
tactfully, a few of the typical feminine shortcomings - wilfulness, indecision,
petty-mindedness, and so on — from which she will be saved through submission
to her appointed masculine head; noting with quiet satisfaction the superiority
of scriptural wisdom over current secular opinion? But the male commentator’s
love of the woman he finds encoded in this text may well have little to do with
the love of Christ for the church. The love of Christ for the church is not a
patronizing love, nor is it a thinly veiled self-satisfaction.
Or are we to adopt
the manner of the contemporary ‘hermeneutics of suspicion’ and denounce the
text as an ideological construct, a building no longer fit for human
habitation? But textual nihilism is an inadequate response to textual optimism,
unless one is committed from the outset to the demolition of the concept of
‘holy scripture’. In an attempt to find a way beyond textual optimism and
textual nihilism, we begin with the modest observation that the selected
passage (Eph. 5.22—33) begins in the middle of a sentence.
MUTUALITY AND SUBJECTIOn [VERSES 22 ± 23)
. . . wives
to your own husbands as to the Lord. (v. 22) ‘Woman’ and ‘man’ (gune
and aner) are here presented in the roles of‘wife’ and ‘husband’.
Marriage is not the only way that woman and man belong together in the Lord,
but it is one such way; and this way is the theme of the passage as a whole
(Eph. 5.22—33). However, in extracting the passage from its context we have
already done violence to it, as the lack of a verb in the first clause
indicates. This is not a self-contained set-piece, capable of independent life
outside its context (as in the case of 1 Cor. 13). It is not a new chapter or
paragraph, opening with the exhortation: ‘Wives, be subject to your husbands .
. . ’[lvi] [lvii] [lviii]
[lix] There is no dividing-line or interval between this
passage and that which precedes it, no conclusion followed by a new start. The
address to women or wives arises from the preceding exhortations with hardly a
pause for breath. Where it is forgotten that this passage is an integral part
of the text known as ‘the Epistle of Paul to the Ephesians’, its interpretation
will be seriously impaired.3 The damage done to
the passage by excising it from its context can only be repaired by grafting it
back in again: by restoring the exhortation to wives and husbands to its
immediate context, but above all by allowing the richness and complexity of the
letter
imperatives in the 'household
code’ (Eph. 5.25, 6.1, 4, 5, 9) — although its position in the sentence is
unusual. The third plural recalls 1 Cor. 14.34.
3 Was the author of this letter really
Paul, and was it originally addressed to the Ephesians? In 1.1, 'in Ephesus’ is
omitted by P46
and by the original form of Codex Sinaiticus and Codex Alexandrinus. Marcion
believed it to have been addressed to the Laodiceans — a deduction from Col.
4.16. The letter was 'perhaps intended as an encyclical, copies being sent to
various churches, of which that at Ephesus was chief’ (B. M. Metzger, A
Textual Commentary on the Greek New Testament, London and New York: United
Bible Societies, 2nd edn 1975, 601). As for the authorship question, it is
widely agreed that if the author was not Paul he nevertheless shows a deep
knowledge of Pauline theology (unlike the author of the Pastoral Epistles). But
in that case, why should he not be Paul? (Is it any harder to think of
Paul as the author of 1 Thessalonians, 1 Corinthians and Ephesians than it is
to think of Beethoven as the composer of the String Quartets Op. 18, 59 and
131?) How far is the present consensus against Pauline authorship simply a
matter of scholarly fashion? The consensus may derive in part from Ernst
Kasemann’s influential 'early catholicism’ thesis, according to which later New
Testament writings such as Ephesians and Acts betray a drift away from the
Pauline gospel of the justification of the ungodly towards a 'catholic’
interest in the church as a topic in its own right. 'A shift of emphasis is
disclosed by the fact that for him [the author of Ephesians] the body of Christ
grows not only into the open world but also . . . into the heights of heaven.
The theme of the church dominates him to such an extent that the church is no
longer mentioned as part of a continuing contrast to the world. The church has
become an independent theme in relation to cosmology, just as it became one
with respect to Christology’ (E. Kasemann, 'Ephesians and Acts’, in L. E. Keck
and J. L. Martyn (eds.), Studies in Luke±Acts, Nashville: Abingdon
Press, 1966, 288 — 97, 296). If one discounts these impressionistic and
inaccurate statements, there is also the question whether the 'meditative-
doxological style of Ephesians’ is conceivable from an author whose preferred
mode is argument and dialectic (289). But Paul does not always argue (compare
Eph. 1.3—14 with Rom. 5.1 — 11). The defence of Pauline authorship in G. B.
Caird’s Paul's Letters from Prison (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976,
11—17) still seems to me to be valid. The issue is of some significance, and
should not be evaded by too easy a recourse to a 'canonical perspective’. One
position makes it possible to see this text as 'the crown of St Paul’s
writings’, while the other can only recommend that it 'should not be wholly
disregarded’ in an account of Pauline theology (respectively, J. A. Robinson, St
Paul's Epistle to the Ephesians, London: Macmillan, 2nd edn 1928, vii; J.
D. G. Dunn, The Theology of Paul the Apostle, Grand Rapids: Eerdmans,
1998, 13n). as
a whole to inform our reading of this part of it. The theme of the letter is
'the many-sided wisdom of God' (Eph. 3.10), and something of this
many-sidedness may perhaps be discernible beneath the surface even of an apparently
one-sided text that counsels female submission to male headship.
In Eph. 5.18-21, two
interrelated imperatives ('Do not be drunk with wine . . . , but be hlled with
the Spirit' (v. 18)) are followed by four participial clauses that give content
to the exhortation to be hlled with the Spirit (vv. 19-21): . . . addressing
one another in psalms and hymns and spiritual songs, singing and making melody
to the Lord with your heart, always andfor everything giving thanks to God the
Father in the name of our Lord Jesus Christ, being subject to one another in
the fear of Christ. . . This is the context in which wives and husbands are
now singled out: . . . wives to your own husbands as to the Lord. Of the
four participial exhortations, the second and third speak of a practice
directed towards the Lord or God (singing and making melody to the Lord, giving
thanks to God the Father), whereas the hrst and fourth speak of a practice
directed towards one another (addressing one another (heautois), being
subject to one another (alleloisj). As in the entire letter up to this
point, the addressees are simply 'the saints at Ephesus, who are faithful in
Christ Jesus' (1.1). They are men and women, parents and children, slave-owners
and slaves, but prior to the 'household code' of 5.22-6.9 they are not
addressed as men or women, parents or children, slave-owners or slaves.[lx] Thus, the exhortations to
thankfulness and to mutual subjection are addressed to all, irrespective of
gender, age or socioeconomic status. It is irrelevant to the exhortation,
'being subject to one another. . .', that one is a male householder or a female
slave, a female householder or a male slave. The various groups do not have to
be addressed separately; indeed they must not be. 'There is one body and
one Spirit, just as you were called in the one hope of your calling; one Lord,
one faith, one baptism, one God and Father of all ...' (4.4—6). In the one
baptism into the one body, distinctions and categories do not cease to exist,
but they are subordinated to a new, common identity. They are relegated to the
background.
This new identity
has a history; it has come into being. Although the addressees have always been
conscious of themselves as men or women, slaves or free, a consciousness of
themselves as ‘Gentiles’, non-Jews, may not previously have been a significant
factor in their identity. Their new identity retrospectively constitutes them
as ‘Gentiles’, only to declare that in the death of Jesus the Jew-Gentile
divide has been removed. ‘There is neither Jew nor Greek’: one new humanity (hena
kainon anthropon, 2.16) has arisen in place of the division, in such a way
that Gentiles enter into the heritage of the apostles and prophets which is
also the heritage of Israel (2.11—22). An expression of the former hostility
may be seen in the offensive way that each group once expressed its abhorrence
of the other. To Jews, Gentiles are, collectively, ‘the foreskin’ (he
akrobustia); to Gentiles, Jews are ‘the circumcision’ (2.11). Women as well
as men are included in these designations, since the male reproductive organ
is the concern of women as well as men. This hostility was a symptom of an
underlying reality: Gentiles really were ‘without Christ, alienated from the
commonwealth of Israel and strangers to the covenants of promise’ (2.12). But
now, in Christ, Gentile and Jew are one. They do not simply cease to be Gentile
or Jew. Paul continues to distinguish ‘we who first hoped in Christ’ from ‘you
also’ who heard the gospel and believed it (1.12—13). Nor does the removal of
the distinction issue in a ‘third race’, without antecedents. Insofar as
Gentiles are now admitted to the heritage of Christ and of Israel, the ‘one new
humanity’ is still a Jewish humanity (no less Jewish for being universal), and
Gentile identity within it is a proselyteidentity. Difference is not erased,
and there are moments when it is important to remember it (mnemoneuete,
2.11). Yet difference has been relativized by the one baptism into the one
body. That is true of the difference between Jew and Gentile, but it is also
true of the difference between male and female, parent and child, slave and
free. The fact that the letter as a whole is addressed to all Christians at
Ephesus, irrespective of gender, age or socioeconomic status, is an indication
that the new, common identity is not just an idea but a genuine social reality,
reflecting the theological reality of the eternal divine oikonomia whose
goal is the summing up (anakephalaiosis) of all things in Christ (1.10).
In the ‘household
code’ (5.22-6.9), it is acknowledged that differences persist within the ‘one
body’ which has hitherto been addressed without differentiation. The new,
common identity relativizes differences, but it does not erase them. Within the
one body, there are still men and women, parents and children, slave-owners and
slaves. They are one but they are also different, just as members of the body
differ from one another within the body’s comprehensive unity (4.7, 16, 25).
Although they participate in Christ’s exaltation into the heavenly realms
(2.6), they do so while remaining on earth. They remain human, they have not
been transformed into angels: indeed, their full humanity is precisely the goal
of the divine oikonomia (4.13), which comprehends things on earth as
well as things in heaven (1.10, cf. 3.15). The differences that are so integral
to human life on earth are not obliterated within the one body, for the one
body is not a gnostic denial of reality but the divinely ordained context
within which human social reality is comprehended and transformed. Thus, an
address to ‘the saints at Ephesus, who are faithful in Christ Jesus’ (1.1) can
in the ‘household code’ acknowledge the differences within the one body by
addressing particular groups - wives, husbands, children, parents, slaves,
slave-owners - before again subsuming the differences into unity in the general
exhortation, ‘Be strong in the Lord . . . ’ (6.10). The address to particular
groups remains relevant to the body as a whole, for the way that wives and
husbands, children and parents, slaves and slave-owners relate to one another
is not a private concern but the concern of the whole body. If, within the one
body, the relationship between a husband and wife is impaired, this is a threat
to ‘the unity of the Spirit’ and ‘the bond of peace’ that bind together the
body as a whole. Within the body there are no purely private concerns; ‘for we
are members one of another’ (4.25).
‘Being subject to
one another in the fear of Christ, wives to your own husbands . . .’
(5.21-2).The difference between woman and man, wife and husband, is neither
eradicated by the new identity nor absolutized. If it had been eradicated,
there could be no speci®c address to wives and husbands; the general,
undifferentiated relationship implied by ‘one another’ would be the only
possibility. As the text stands, however, the mutuality of ‘one another’ does
indicate that, although the gender difference is important, it is not
all-important. Man and woman may be addressed as man or as woman,
but they may also be addressed together, as humans who participate in the new
humanity and who all alike share responsibility for the form of life in which
it is expressed. If this new humanity is a true disclosure of ‘human nature’,
it cannot be said of the latter ‘that neither man nor woman can manifest nor
experience its totality’, since ‘each gender possesses or represents only one
part of it’ (Irigaray).[lxi] Man and woman alike participate in the totality of
human nature, and they do so as man and woman but also as human.
Human nature is no more an unmediated ‘two’ than it is an undifferentiated
‘one’, and the basis for this assertion is the fact that Jesus establishes
peace by ‘making the two one’ (Eph. 2.14). One does not eradicate two (there
are still Jews and Gentiles, men and women); it is a third that mediates
between them and thus establishes the peace that is their original telos.
In the summing up of all things in Christ, the two are one without ceasing to
be two; and Jesus’ ability to comprehend the two derives not from any
absolutizing of a limited (male) experience but from his divine vocation as the
bringer of peace. The oneness that he establishes is not a oneness without
difference but ‘the oneness of the Spirit in the bond of peace’ (4.3). It is
again the doctrine of the immanent trinity that provides the conceptual model
for this coinherence of unity and plurality.
This
coinherence is for mally illustrated by the exhortation to be ‘subject to one
another in the fear of Christ, wives to your own husbands . . . ’ (5.21-2), and
it is also closely related to the specific content of the exhortation. To be
subject to another is to give precedence to the claim of the other over the
claim one might otherwise advance on one’s own behalf. Mutual subjection is
the only possible form of life for those who are members of one another within
the one body (4.4, 25). As Paul argues elsewhere, to refuse this subjection is
to deny that one is part of the body. Yet ‘the eye cannot say to the hand, “I
have no need of you’’, nor again the head to the feet, “I have no need of
you’’’ (1 Cor. 12.21). Rather than asserting an absurd claim to independence,
we are to conform to a divinely appointed order in which ‘the members have the
same care for one another’ (v. 25). Since this subjection is mutual rather than
unilateral, the precedence given to the claim of the other also ensures that my
own claim is attended to and is not forgotten — not as the result of my
self-assertion but within the context of an interdependence in which my claim
on another can never be detached from the other’s claim on me. To say, ‘Be
subject to one another’ is simply to say, ‘We are members of one another.’
Because we are to be
subject to one another, wives are to be subject to husbands. So closely is the
address to wives bound to the preceding exhortation that there is no need to
repeat the verb. The context of the subjection of wives to husbands is this mutual
subjection to one another. Yet in singling out the subjection of wives without
a corresponding appeal to husbands to be subject to their wives, there appears
to be a shift from mutual to unilateral subjection. In the following verse (v.
23), the explanation that ‘the husband is the head of the wife’ confirms this
shift: subjection is now a unilateral subjection to a superior who is merely
the passive recipient of this subjection without the active response of
subjecting himself to his wife. The address to wives has immediately brought us
into the sphere of an understanding of marriage in which the male exercises
authority over the female and in which the female is bound to submit to that
authority. The text takes it for granted that marriage will take this form,
just as it takes it for granted that the household will include not only
parents and children but also slaves. The crucial question is whether, in the
end, the text merely provides a new religious legitimation for the existing
form or whether, taking the existing form as its starting-point, it
nevertheless transforms it. If Jesus 'is our peace, who has made us both one'
(2.14), is this a peace that affirms existing social structures by denying the
legitimacy of conflict, or does it overcome a conflict endemic to the
structures themselves?
Ideology or utopia:
a familiar antithesis that will also determine the relation of the interpreter
to the text — for an ideological text is a 'bad' text, whereas a utopian text
is a 'good' one. These value judgments have their theological warrant in the
assertion that Jesus came not to af®r m what already exists but to transform
it. But texts may prove recalcitrant when subjected to this critical
antithesis. It is not always easy to determine exactly where complicity in an
existent form ends and where subversion or transformation begins. Can it be
said that the Christ of Ephesians 5 either 'functions as a legitimation
of patriarchal marriage' or 'transforms patriarchal marriage by
subjecting it to the criterion of love'?6 Common
to both positions is the assumption that the text is a simple entity with a
single underlying tendency, either 'reactionary' or 'progressive', bad or good.
In both of its forms, this assumption is itself 'reactionary': for the text is
measured against the yardstick of a pre-existing criterion as to what is to
count as good or bad, a criterion that it can only confirm (or 'legitimate').
Measured against the prior criterion, the text may be judged to be 'good' or
'bad'; but either way, the prior criterion judges itself to be 'good' and uses
the text to reinforce and legitimate its positive self-image. The criterion is
the basis for interpretation, the field upon which the interpretative
game is played, and this excludes a priori not only the possibility that
the criterion is simply wrong but also the more subtle possibility that it is
not given in advance but can be adequately articulated only in and through
6 Ben Witherington finds in this passage
a 'new approach to marriage' which is 'Paul's deliberate attempt to reform the
patriarchal structure of his day' (Women and the Genesis of Christianity,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990, 156). On the other hand, Sarah J.
Tanzer argues that Eph. 5.22 — 6.9 (in contrast to 2.14) 'is clearly not about
equals but about hierarchy; it does not break down dividing walls but rather
establishes them and teaches one to live within those hierarchical bounds'
('Ephesians', in E. Schussler Fiorenza (ed.), Searching the Scriptures,
vol. 11: A Feminist Commentary, New York: Crossroad, 1994, 325—48, 341).
Both views simplify the passage by ignoring its anomalies.
critical
dialogue with the text; that the criterion or criteria by which the text is to
be assessed become clear only at the conclusion of the act of interpretation,
not at the beginning. A nuanced hermeneutic along these lines is especially
necessary in the case of a text as complex as Ephesians 5.22-33.
If one is forced to
decide that this is either a ‘good’ text or a ‘bad’ one, the basic tendency of
the present interpretation is to try to read it as a ‘good’ text (like 1 Cor.
11.2-16 - on which see chapter 2 - but unlike 1 Cor. 14.33-5 or 1 Tim. 2.11-15,
which are clearly ‘bad’ texts). But whether or not it turns out to be a ‘good’
text, it is certainly a very odd one, and the ®rst of its oddities has
already become clear. An exhortation to mutual subjection, (irmly grounded in
Pauline ecclesiology, shows an unaccountable drift towards unilateral
subjection when the exhortation is redirected speci®cally towards wives. The
text is in contradiction to itself, and the question is how far it is capable
of addressing and overcoming its own contradictions.
For
the husband is head of the wife as Christ is head of the church, and is himself
saviour of the body.
(v. 23) An explanation is given of the subjection required of wives, and it appears
to conhrm that this subjection is unilateral. The subjection of wives is their
recognition of the higher status of the husband, just as the church subjects
itself to Christ in acknowledgment that he is its Lord.
The husband is head
of the wife, Christ is head of the church: two male heads, exalted over two
female subordinates? But maleness operates differently on the two sides of the
equation. On the first side, maleness is integral to the argument. The
husband-wife relationship is obviously a particular expression of the
male-female relationship; an assertion about husband and wife is as such also
an assertion about gender. But the relationship between Christ and the church
is not so obviously a particular expression of the male-female relationship. Christ
is the head of the church and Christ is male, but his maleness is only relevant
if the Christ-church relation is located within the polarity of male and
female. Christ is a male, but he is also a Galilean Jew who died in his early
thirties: all of these facts are necessary for correct identification of the
bearer of the name or title ‘Christ’, but they belong to the background of the
assertion that ‘Christ is head of the church’ and not to its foreground. It is
possible that, on the basis of the husband-wife relationship in the first half
of the equation, gender is projected onto the Christ-church relationship in the
second half; that question will be discussed in connection with the following
verse. But as things stand here, it is not clear that the statement ‘Christ is
the head of the church’ entails a maleness corresponding to the husband’s. It
is not said that the husband is suited to a role analogous to Christ’s because
Christ too is male.
Elsewhere
in the New Testament, Christ’s maleness is everywhere assumed but only rarely
placed in the foreground. It comes briefly into sharp focus in the dialogue
between Jesus and the Samaritan woman, especially at the point where the
returning disciples ‘were surprised that he was talking with a woman’ (Jn. 4.27,
in contrast to vv. 7—8, where the primary social boundary that Jesus crosses is
the one between Jew and Samaritan, not male and female). The Pauline metaphor
of Christ as ‘head’ is elsewhere not explicitly gendered — even in
1
Corinthians 11.3, where Christ
is the head not of a feminine ekklesia but of ‘every man’, a category
which he himself seems here to transcend. The bridegroom-bride image, derived
from Old Testament prophetic texts about the relation between Yahweh and
Israel, occurs in its full form only in John 3.29,
2
Corinthians 12.2 and Revelation
19.7, 21.2, 9, 22.17 (where the marriage partners are a lamb and a city);
elsewhere, the ®gure of the bridegroom consistently appears without the bride
(Matt. 9.15, 22.2, 25.1 — 13). The maleness of Christ is theologically
important only in the event of his circumcision as an eight-day- old child (Lk.
2.21, Col. 2.11), where it is correlated with his Jewishness and his
bodiliness. The male—female polarity is less prominent here than the polarity
of Jew and Gentile, partly because maleness is established here by the
reference to the ‘male member’ and not by reference to the female.
The New
Testament’s lack of interest in Christ’s maleness is consistent with the
suggestion that the husband is not head of the wife because he is of the same
sex as Christ, the head of the church. There is an analogy between the two
headships, but no rationale for this analogy is provided. More signi®cant is
the question of what it means for the husband to be ‘head of the wife as Christ
is head of the church . . . ’ It is not said simply that he is head of the
wife. If that were all, the assumption would be that to be ‘head’ is to ful®l a
role whose duties and privileges are already well known. But the husband does
not ®ll a well-known role. He is head of the wife as and only as
Christ is head of the church. It is not said that his role is the same
as Christ’s, only that it is like Christ’s (and, being ‘like’ rather
than ‘the same’, also unlike Christ’s). The unlikeness between Christ
and the husband is so obvious that one wonders if the husband has here been
promoted beyond his abilities. The husband is not ‘head of the church’, he is
not ‘saviour of the body’, he is not saviour of his wife, he is not the object
of her thanksgiving and song (cf. 5.18-19). But he is the object of her
subjection, insofar as he is called to ful®l the role of a Christ-like
headship. What is the nature of such a role?
As ‘head over all
things’ (1.22), Christ has been exalted ‘far above [huperanO] every rule
and authority and power and lordship’ (1.21). Is the husband exalted far above
his wife? Yet all Christians - men, women, old, young, slaves, free -
participate together in the exaltation of Christ. It is not said only of
men that God has raised them with Christ and made them sit with him in the
heavenly realms (2.6); nor is it men alone who in the strength of the Lord wage
war against the world rulers of this present darkness (6.10—12). On the
contrary, the exhortation to ‘be strong in the Lord’ (6.10) marks the closing
up of the distinctions drawn in the ‘household code’ of 5.22—6.9. But the
concept of exaltation or elevation alone does not adequately characterize
Christ’s headship. In Paul’s interpretation of Psalms 68.19 (LXX), there is no
ascent without a corresponding descent. ‘What does “he ascended’’ mean, but
that he also descended into the lower parts of the earth? He who descended is
the same as he who ascended far above [huperanO] all the heavens, so
that he might ®ll all things’ (Eph. 4.9—10). If the one who descended is ‘the
same’ as the one who ascended, the descent in question is the descent from
heaven in the incarnation; a descent from the heights into the depths which is
not simply cancelled out by the return from the depths into the heights, since
otherwise Paul would hardly stress the identity of the one who descended with
the one who ascended.7 The headship of Christ over all things is not a
matter of ascent alone; it is not only compatible with the movement of
descent into the depths, it is constituted by it no less than by the
corresponding movement of ascent into the heights. Headship over all things and
over the church is the goal of the one who ascended into the heights because he
descended into the depths; it discloses his nature as the one who descended and
ascended. It is not the case that the depths are alien to him whereas the
heights are his true home. He is truly himself in the depths as well as the
heights ± so much so that he would not be himself were he (by some impossibility)
to be debarred from the depths and con- ®ned to the heights.8 Otherwise
it could not be said that the
7 If the ‘descent’ of Eph. 4.9 is the
descent into Sheol or Hades — as J. A. Robinson argues, on the basis of verbal
parallels to Pss. 62.10, 118.15 LXX (Ephesians, 180) — this must still
be seen as the end-point of a descent that begins with the incarnation, if the
descent is to match the ascent (cf. Phil. 2.6—8). But ta katotera [mere] tes
ges may mean no more than 'this lower earth’, which is ‘low’ in contrast to
heaven. More significant is the possibility that the descent is subsequent
to the ascent, and refers to the coming of the Spirit as the giver of the gifts
referred to in Eph. 4.11. ‘This is the descent of Christ to His Church alluded
to in ii.17, ‘‘came and preached’’; [and] in iii.17, ‘‘that Christ may dwell in
your hearts’’ . . .’ (T K. Abbott, The Epistles to the Ephesians and to the
Colossians, ICC, Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1897, 116). This would be
ruled out by the insertion of proton after katebe (the majority
reading), but this appears to be secondary. (The majority reading does indicate
that this text was generally read as a reference to the incarnation —
and/or descent into Hades.) But a reference to the Spirit is in any case
unlikely here: (1) The purpose of the descent that corresponds to the ascent is
said to be ‘that he might ®ll all things’ (4.10), not that he might bestow
gifts (4.11). (2) In the psalm quotation in 4.8, the giving of gifts is the
prerogative of the ascended Christ (edoken in v. 11 refers back
to the quotation). (3) An identification of Christ and Spirit is incompatible
with the clear distinctions between the ‘one Spirit’, the ‘one Lord’ and the
‘one God’ in 4.4—6 (cf. 1 Cor. 12.4—6).
8 As Barth argues, ‘True Godhead in the
New Testament is being in the absolute freedom of love, and therefore the being
of the Most High who is high and almighty and eternal and righteous and
glorious not also but precisely in his lowliness’ (Church Dogmatics iv/1
(1953), ET Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1956, 191). Thus, ‘Jesus Christ is the
Son of God and as such, in conformity with the divine nature, the Most High who
humbles himself and in that way is exalted and very high’ (192). The close
correlation of descent and ascent in Eph. 4.9—10 is important for Barth’s
presentation of ‘the way of the Son of God into the far country’ (iv/1, §59.1)
and ‘the homecoming of the Son of man’ (iv/2, §64.2) as two sides of a single
divine action. As Eph. 4.9 — 10 confirms, ‘It is not... a matter of two different
and successive actions, but of a single action in purpose of the movement of
descent and ascent was ‘that he might fill all things’ (4.10) — making them his
permanent dwelling-place, irrespective of whether they are high or low.
Otherwise he would bring about no true gathering together or anakephalaiosis
of things in heaven and things on earth (1.10).
If the husband is to
be head of the wife as Christ is head of the church, he must, like Christ, be
familiar with the depths as well as the heights. If so, the wife’s subjection
to her husband as her head is anything but straightforward. His headship is no
longer just an elevated status. Like Christ (but also very unlike him), he
comes ‘not to be served but to serve’ (Mk. 10.45); not to receive subjection
(as is the way of ‘those who are supposed to rule over the Gentiles’ (10.42)),
but to subject himself. Starting from the conventional view that his wife is
bound to subject herself to him as her head, he has learned from Christ that
‘whoever would be great among you must be your servant, and whoever would be
®rst among you must be slave of all’ (10.43—4). The wife too starts from the
conventional view, but must learn from the church’s subjection to Christ what
it is to subject oneself to one who has ®rst subjected himself to her. The form
of‘patriarchal marriage’ is maintained: the wife must submit to the husband as
to her head. But behind the facade, its substance is subverted and transfor
med. The bridging of the gulf between above and below by Christ the reconciler
is, if not the abolition, at least the deconstruction of patriarchal
marriage. The flat contradiction between the mutual submission of Ephesians
5.21 and the unilateral submission ofv. 22 is already a sign of the
deconstructive process in operation.
THE MYSTERY OF CHRIST [VERSES 24± 27)
But
as the church is subject to Christ, so also the wives to their husbands, in
everything,
(v. 24) The husband is the head of the wife ‘as’ (hos)
which each of the two elements is
related to the other and can be known and understood only in this relationship:
the going out of God only as it aims at the coming in of man; the coming in of
man only as the goal and outworking of the going out of God; and the whole in
its original and proper form only as the being and history of the oneJesus
Christ’ (iv/2,
21).
Christ
is head of the church; wives are therefore to be subject to their husbands 'as'
(hos) the church is subject to Christ. Even if the 'head' metaphor does
not in itself give unqualihed support to male supremacy, it is obvious that in
this passage the relationship between Christ and the church is brought into
close connection with the relationship of male and female. But what is entailed
in the twofold 'as'? If the relation of Christ to the church legitimates the
relation of husband and wife, what is the signihcance here of Christ's maleness
and the feminine gender of ekklesia? How far is there not only a
grounding of the malefemale relation in the Christ-church relation, but also a
corresponding projection of the male—female relation onto the Christ-church
relation? The result of this would be that the asymmetry of the male—female
relation (in the form of the wife's subjection to the man as head) would be
grounded in a Christchurch relation itself now construed as a male-female
relationship. The Christ-church relation would then be the transcendental,
original pattern of the human male-female relation; a kind of Platonic form.
Corresponding to the headship of Christ over the church there would be a
headship of man over woman, derived not from the fall (as Gen. 3.16 implies)
but from creation itself and from the heavenly archetype that precedes
creation. Gender inequality would then be grounded in transcendental ontology.
Ephesians 5 is certainly open to a platonizing reading along these lines. The
question is whether it requires it.
Towards the end of
his 'theological aesthetics', The Glory of the Lord (Herrlichkeit,
1961-9), Hans Urs von Balthasar explores the relationship between the New
Testament usage of 'glory' (doxa) and human sociality.[lxii] Following Barth, von Balthasar understands the
relationship between man and woman as 'the basic form of human togetherness',
and ®nds theological and exe- getical warrant for this claim in the Genesis
creation narratives and in the New Testament's appropriation of 'the metaphor
of the nuptiality between God and Israel' (vii.473, citing Hos. 2.19, Is.
54.4-8, 61.10, 62.4, Ez. 16.7-63, to which might be added the whole of Hos.
1—3, together with later recurrences of the prostitution-motif (4.10—15,
5.3—4); Jer. 3.1—20, 13.26—7, 31.2, Ez. 23.1—49). In Ephesians 5, the Old
Testament themes of creation and ‘covenantal nuptiality’ are ‘bound together
into a New Testament synthesis’ (The Glory of the Lord vn. 480). In this
passage, it is clear that Paul begins ‘by projecting his thought in advance
from the creaturely, sexual sphere (which is the subject of his exhortation) to
the soteriological sphere’. Thus the Church becomes a female person, ‘a reality
that is pre-existent in God’s election of her’, the bride of Christ. ‘The
relationship between Christ and the Church . . . goes far beyond the natural
relationship of the sexes, which ®nds itself subsumed by the former
relationship and given a point of reference utterly superior to itself’ (480).
But its superiority does not lie in any transcending of gender; in this
relationship, the creaturely reality of gender ®nds its apotheosis. The divine
election that precedes the creation of the world (Eph. 1.4—6) is the election
of the bride of Christ, and the sexual relationship of man and woman must
therefore be seen ‘as fundamentally related over and above itself to an
eternal, holy and spotless standing before God, in the love of the incarnate
Christ for his bride, which is the Church . . . ’ (482). This marriage,
eternally decreed by God, becomes a historical reality when the beloved Son
‘shed[s] his blood as a human being and as a man for his bride — which is
undeniably a human, feminine bride — in order to give her from himself the form
that is to be hers for ever’ (483). This form is that of a Marian submission:
the existence of the redeemed person is transformed into ‘the obedientfiat
that the Church speaks to God, the perfect hupotassesthai en panti, “submission
in everything’’ (Eph. 5.24)’ (483). This uninhibited gendering of the church
gives corresponding prominence to the maleness of Christ, the bridegroom — and
also to that of the bridegroom’s father. The feminine ekklesia submits
to the masculine Christ, in accordance with the divine decree that established
this archetypal male—female relationship before the foundation of the world. As
in the conjunction in the Timaeus between the paternal demiurge and the
maternal receptacle, the relationship of gender contains all things and is
itself contained by nothing. We find ourselves in a world in gendered relation
to a gendered deity. Feminine submission to masculine headship is the basic
principle of this relation.
In §45
of the Church Dogmatics (‘Man [Der Mensch] in his Determination
as the Covenant-Partner of God’, iii/2 [1948]),[lxiii] Karl Barth develops an account of the male-female
relationship as the basic and original form of the I-Thou relationship that
establishes humanity as, essentially and from the first, co-humanity (Mitmenschlichkeit).
The essential nature of the human creature is disclosed in the figure of Jesus,
who is ‘man for God’ (§44.1) and ‘man for others’ (§45.1). ‘From the first, in
the very fact that he is human, Jesus is not without his fellow-humans, but to
them and with them and for them’ (209). Jesus’ being for his fellow-humans
corresponds to his being for God, and there is an analogia relationis
between his human existence for God and for others and the relationality of the
inner-trinitarian divine life: thus in Jesus it is disclosed that human being
is being in the imago Dei (219-20). This disclosure underlies the
phenomenological analysis of human being as cohumanity that follows (§45.2),
where Barth analyses the phenomena of eye contact, mutual speech and hearing,
mutual help, all willingly undertaken, in the light of the basic thesis that
humanity is co-humanity. In sum:
In
its basic form humanity is co-humanity. Everything else which is to be
described as human nature and essence stands under this sign to the extent that
it is human. If it is not co-human, if it is not in some way an approximation
to being in the encounter of I and Thou, it is not human . . . Man is in fact
co-human [Der Mensch ist mitmenschlich]. He is in fact in the encounter
of I and Thou. This is true even though he may contradict it both in theory and
in practice; even though he may pretend to be human in isolation and produce
anthropologies to match. In so doing he merely proves that he is contradicting
himself, not that he can divest himself of this basic form [Grundform]
of his humanity. He has no choice to be co-human or something else. His being
has this basic form. (285—6)
At this
point (§45.3), Barth identihes the male—female relation as the primary form of
the Mitmenschlichkeit that is human nature:
In
the whole reach of human life there is no abstractly human [kein abstrakt
Menschliches] but only concretely masculine and feminine being, feeling,
willing, thinking, speaking, conduct and action, and only concretely masculine
and feminine co-existence and cooperation [Zusammensein und Zusammenwirken]
in all these things . . . Man is to woman and woman to man supremely the Other,
the fellow-human [der andere Mensch, der Mitmensch], to see and to be
seen by whom, to speak with and to listen to whom, to receive from and to
render assistance to whom is necessarily a supreme human need and problem and
fulfilment, so that whatever may take place between man and man and woman and
woman is only as it were a preliminary and accompaniment for this true
encounter between human and fellow-human, for this true being in co-humanity
(286, 288)
As Barth
notes, 1 Corinthians 11.11 — 12 might be regarded as the text for this whole
section: ‘Nevertheless neither is woman without man nor man without woman in
the Lord . . . ’ (309). Man and woman belong together. They exist as man and as
woman only in relation to the other, and without this belonging together there
is no humanity.
All this evokes
echoes from previous chapters. ‘What we need is to discover how two can
be made which one day could become a one in that third which is love’
(Irigaray, An Ethics of Sexual Difference, 66): and what is here
presented as a project for the present and the future is also the reality of
human nature, given in creation. Like Irigaray, Barth is aware of the pervasive
tendency to reduce the two to one, rather than treating the one as a
third; and he is also aware that this characteristically takes the form of the
absolutizing of the male — as in the case of Nietzsche. According to Barth,
individualistic anthropology reaches its most extreme form in Ecce Homo,
with its claim that the human is supremely disclosed in Nietzsche himself. It
is consistent with this that he has ‘no use at all for women’ but ‘can only
ignore them or heap upon them scorn and his choicest invective’ (CD 111/2,
234). In her Marine Lover: Of Friedrich Nietzsche (1980), Irigaray
confronts precisely this problem, addressing the philosopher directly, in the
second person singular. Like Barth, she regards Nietzsche’s misogynistic traits
not as an isolated blemish but as a symptom of what is at stake in his entire
philosophical project. ‘Behold the man’: here, homo is a man without
woman, a man in isolation — and therefore, according to both Barth and Irigaray,
a man in contradiction to the basic reality of human nature as the co-humanity
of male and female. Nietzsche’s homo is an extreme version of the much
broader phenomenon of man-in-isolation, which (according to Barth) may be
traced historically to the fact that ‘for so many centuries the philosophical
and theological study of the West was the cloister-cell, from whose distinctive
I-speculation in the absence of the Thou it has been difficult to break free
even outside the cloister’ (290). Further back still, there lies the world of
the Greeks and their eros — or rather, the world of Greek males. ‘For
all the eroticism of theory and practice, this was a man’s world in which there
was no real place for woman; and for this reason it was necessarily a world of
the I without the Thou, and therefore a world of the I wandering without limit
or object, a demonic and tyrannical world’ (290). It is true that in the Symposium,
it is a woman (Diotima) who initiates Socrates into the higher mysteries of
eros. But as Irigaray points out, Diotima is not actually present at this
all-male drinking-party. ‘Diotima is not the only example of a woman whose
wisdom, especially about love, is reported in her absence by a man’ (Ethics,
20). As we have seen, Irigaray identifies a further form of the basic error of
reducing two to one (a masculine one) in the tendency to assign to woman
opposite and complementary qualities to the qualities that man assigns to
himself. Man projects onto woman what he thinks he wants of her, thus recreating
her in the image of his own need and depriving her of her own subjectivity.
Barth is similarly critical of the notion of complementarity, although not
quite for this reason. It may be said, for example, that man is more interested
in the objective and the outer, woman in the subjective and inner; that man is
inclined towards freedom, woman towards dependence; that man prefers to wander,
woman to stay at home. ‘Statements such as these may sometimes be ventured as
hypotheses, but cannot be represented as knowledge or dogma because real man
and real woman are far too complex and contradictory to be summed up in
portrayals of this nature’ (CD 111/2, 287). Irigaray too insists on the
fact of difference but regards its content as something that must be discovered
in encounter and that cannot be precisely specified in advance.
So far so good?
Unfortunately, Barth does wish to say one thing about the content of the
difference, ignoring his own caveat about the complexity of ‘real man and real
woman’. Man has precedence over woman. He is first, she is second. This is not
(he thinks) ‘inferiority’: without woman man could not be man, and he is as
dependent on her for his manhood as she is on him for her womanhood. But where
there is a ‘relationship of super- and subordination’, can ‘superiority’ and
‘inferiority’ really be excluded? The nature and scope of man’s headship and
woman’s subordination to it cannot be de®ned but must be ‘constantly
experienced in their mutual exchanges and co-existence’ (287). But what if one
cannot ®nd it in the mutual exchanges of this co-existence (however hard one
looks), or if one finds it only in forms one cannot regard as normative? Why
does Barth insist on this understanding of difference as the difference of super
and sub, over and under, above and below, a difference of elevation,
although his analysis of the basic form of the I-Thou relationship constitutive
of human nature gives absolutely no grounds for this? The answer is that, like
von Balthasar after him, Barth ®nds the exegetical key to his theological
anthropology in Ephesians 5. It is only because the whole range of scriptural
teaching on the male-female relation is in this passage ‘set before us so
authoritatively and perspicuously’ that we find the ‘courage’ to consider
questions that might otherwise seem beyond us (313). In particular, there is
the question why humankind was created as male and female. In the light
of Ephesians 5, the answer is as follows:
Behind
the relationship of man and woman as we meet it in the picture of Genesis 2 and
the Song of Songs there stands the controlling original of the relationship
between the God Yahweh-Elohim and his people Israel. Behind these passages
there stands Old Testament prophecy. And according to the insight which continually
breaks through, the sum of all truth and actuality, which is thus also the
beginning and end of all things, the secret of creation and its consummation,
is the very different duality merely reflected in the nature of man — that of
God and man in their co-existence in the concrete form of the covenant
established by God between himself and his people Israel. This duality ... is
the original [das Urbild] of which the essence of the human as the being
of man and woman can only be the reflection and copy [Reflex und Abbild].
Man is primarily and properly Yahweh, and woman primarily and properly Israel [Der
Mann heisst zuerst und eigentlichJahwe und die Frau heisst zuerst und
eigentlich Israel]. (297)
How does
the Old Testament know all this? The old hermeneutical principle holds good: vetus
testamentum in novo patet.
The
New Testament answers that the covenant between Jesus Christ and his community
was in the beginning, the first and proper object of the divine will and plan
and election, and the internal basis of creation. This covenant is the original
of the Old Testament original, the relationship between Yahweh and Israel, and
therefore the original of the relationship between man and woman. It is on the
basis of this original that the intra-creaturely relationship has its dignity
and necessity . . . (299)
Man is
Yahweh, woman is Israel; or rather, man is Jesus Christ, woman is the church.
Conversely, Christ is Man, the church is Woman, and the relationship between
this Man and this Woman is the innermost content of the eternal divine decree
and therefore ‘the sum of all truth and actuality, . . . the beginning and end
of all things, the secret of creation and its consummation’. As in von
Balthasar, we find ourselves in a world (supposed to be the world of Eph. 5) in
which the male— female relation is the container that contains all things and
is contained by nothing. In this strikingly Platonic world, the human
male—female relation is a ‘copy’ of a transcendental, heavenly ‘original’ that
is itself gendered.11
11 The issue of subordination is much
more prominent in this section (§45.3) than in Barth’s later, more extensive
treatment of the male—female relation in CD 111/4, 116—240 (§54.1). In
the light of the latter section, it might be possible to regard difference
rather than order as Barth’s primary concern in this area — the
'difference’ presupposed in 'co-humanity’, rather than the difference of mere
heterogeneity (as, sometimes, in Irigaray). This conception of difference does
not entail any prior judgments about the roles appropriate and inappropriate to
women: 'Life is richer, and above all the command of God is more manifold, than
might appear from preconceived opinions’ (111/4, 154). Although Barth (like
Virginia Woolf) finds in the
There
are several interrelated issues here. One is the absolutizing of gender. That
is also present in Irigaray, at moments where her ‘ethics of sexual difference’
take a metaphysical turn towards a post-Christian neo-polytheism in which the
banished gods and goddesses again walk the earth in human flesh. A second issue
is the ‘vertical’ account of sexual difference (absent in Irigaray, present in
Ephesians 5 — although by no means as unproblematically as Barth and von
Balthasar assume). A third issue, the product of the first two, is the
projection of this vertical difference onto the divine—human relation. Does
this projection really occur in Ephesians 5? Wives are to submit to their
husbands ‘as’ (hos) the church submits to Christ (Eph. 5.24). Is the
church a Wife and is Christ her Husband? Nothing compels one to read into this
passage the bridal language of Revelation or the prophetic image of Israel as
the adulterous wife.12 ‘As’ does indeed imply an analogy, even an analogia
entis if both divine and human ens are inherently relational. But
‘as’ also implies the dissimilarity or limit that is as integral to the
structure of analogy as similarity. ‘The kingdom of God is as [hos] a man who
casts seed upon the earth . . . ’ (Mk. 4.26). The man does so in accordance
with the divine decree that he should be a tiller of the ground (cf. Gen. 1.29,
2.5, 15, 3.17—19); and the parable suggests that there is an analogy between
this divinely ordained human activity and the divine action signi®ed
modern feminist movement a 'desire on the part of
women to occupy the position and fulfil the function of men’ (111/4, 155), he
is also aware of its positive significance in freeing women from 'the
uncalled-for illusions of man, and his attempts to dictate what is suitable for
her and what is not’ {ibid.}. It would be wrong to regard the notion of
the gendered heavenly archetype of the male—female relation as the sum and goal
of Barth’s treatment of gender.
12 The prophetic depiction of the
covenant as the (unhappy) marriage of Yahweh and Israel is one among a number
of images of the covenant, and should not be given the systematic status Barth
attributes to it. Even in Hosea, the probable source of this image, Israel is
to Yahweh not only an unfaithful wife but also a stubborn heifer (Hos. 4.16), an
unturned cake (7.8), a dove (7.11), a treacherous bow (7.16), a wild ass (8.9),
grapes (9.10), a luxuriant vine (10.1), a trained heifer (10.11), a child
learning to walk (11.3 — 4), a child in the womb (13.13) and a lily (14.5); and
Yahweh is to Israel not only a wronged husband but also a moth, dry rot (5.12),
a fowler (7.12), a loving parent (11.3 — 4), a lion, a leopard and a bear
(5.14, 13.7 — 8), dew (14.5) and an evergreen cypress (14.8). Although the
husband-wife image is able to say more than these other images, it is not clear
that its status is any different from, for example, the parent-child image of
11.3—4.
by ‘the
kingdom of God’. On this basis, would it be appropriate to ®nd ‘the beginning
and end of all things, the secret of creation and its consummation’ in human
agricultural activity, as well as in marriage? If this is inappropriate in the
one case, can it be appropriate in the other? ‘As’ denotes an analogy, and to
push an analogy beyond its limit, in the hope that it will yield a metaphysic,
is simply to destroy it.[lxiv]
Husbands,
love your wives, as Christ loved the church and gave himself up for it .. . (v. 25) The
household code is concerned with three relationships: between wives and
husbands, children and parents, slaves and their owners. Each of the six groups
is addressed, and is exhorted to ful®l the task to which it is called in
relation to its opposite number. Thus the subject of an obligation is always
also the object of a corresponding obligation. I have a duty to the other, but
the other also has a duty towards me. Wives are to be subject to their
husbands, but they are also to be the objects of their husbands’ love. Children
are to obey their parents, but they are themselves to be treated fairly,
without arbitrariness (Eph. 6.1-4). Slaves are to obey their masters and
mistresses, since in doing so they serve Christ himself; but if their owners
represent Christ passively, as the object of service, their own conduct towards
their servants must be actively Christ-like in its refusal to resort to threats
(6.5-9). The action required of all six groups is not the unilinear action of a
subject towards a passive object that lies outside the scope of the address; it
belongs in the context of reciprocal action. The wife is to be subject
to the husband who loves her as Christ loved the church: the pairing of the
addressees and the exhortations ensures that each of the exhortations is set
within a dialogical movement in which each addressee is both subject and object
of exhortation, and is subject as object and object as subject.
Beneath the surface of the formal symmetry, everything is in constant circular
motion. Each of the six groups may impair the to-and-fro, dialogical movement
with its opposite number, or even bring it to a halt. The wife may refuse to be
subject, the husband may fail to love, the child or slave may disobey, the
parent or slave-owner may resort to arbitrariness and violence. Is the
exhortation still binding on the other party when its own being as the object
of a corresponding obligation is overlooked? The problem is particularly acute
for the subordinate partner in each pair (wives, children and slaves). But
there can be no prescribing in advance for extreme situations in which the
attempt to ful®l one's own obligation is rendered meaningless or damaging by
the other's refusal to acknowledge that obligation is mutual. Even under
‘normal' conditions, the appropriate form for the ful®lment of one's obligation
will not always be easy to determine. All of the exhortations are therefore
subject to the quali®cation: ‘Do not be foolish, but understand what the will
of the Lord is' (Eph. 5.17, cf. v. 10). Attempts to codify the living, active
will and guidance of the risen Lord are necessary, but they can never
adequately represent the content of that will and guidance, they can only
point towards it.
Wives are to be
subject, husbands are to love, children and slaves are to be obedient, fathers
are to bring up children in the discipline and instruction of the Lord,
slave-owners are no longer to threaten. But is it only husbands who
love, and not wives, children and parents? If the love in question is Christian
agape, can even slaves and slave-owners be exempted from the obligation to love
one another? Agape comprehends Christian living in its entirety, and there is
no relationship that lies outside its scope, as though at some point agape
reached its limit. ‘Love never ends' (1 Cor. 13.8): it is not subject to limit.
‘The will of the Lord' that we are to ‘understand', within our concrete
circumstances, will never be anything other than love. We are therefore to
‘walk in love, as Christ loved us and gave himself up for us, a fragrant
offering and sacrifice to God' (5.1—2). The comprehensive pattern for Christian
living is the ‘obedience unto death’ that is also a ‘love unto death’ that
draws Jesus to Jerusalem, in order to undergo the sufferings of Gethsemane and
Golgotha for our sake. Can this action of his really serve as the paradigm for
Christian living in its entirety? To understand it as such, we (not on our own,
but in the company of ‘all the saints’) must receive from the indwelling Spirit
who is also the indwelling Christ the ability ‘to comprehend what is the length
and breadth and height and depth, and to know the love of Christ that surpasses
knowledge’, and thus to live as those who are ‘rooted and grounded in love’
(3.16-19). To understand Jesus’ self-sacrifice in its full dimensions is to see
it as the moment in which the divine plan ‘to unite all things in him, things in
heaven and things on earth’ (1.10) comes to fruition — and thus to see one’s
own life and the relationships in which it is set no longer as the whole but as
comprehended within the immeasurable divine love that embraces all things and
that wills their reconciliation and peace (cf. Col. 1.20). Love does not call
us to new ways of relating to our neighbour without first setting us within
these incomparably broad horizons. To be ‘rooted and grounded’ in this
love is therefore the bestowal of space and freedom even within the constraints
of relationships that may appear to confine us within the narrowest of limits:
the relationships of wives and husbands, children and parents, slaves and
slave-owners. As the love of Christ embraces these relationships and the individuals
held within them, so all alike — and not only husbands — are called to ‘walk in
love’. This love is present in the depths as well as the heights, and its reach
extends to those who are far off as well as those who are near. It dissolves
the sharp outlines of asymmetrical, hierarchical relationships liable to
hostility and violence, in order that they may attain to ‘the measure of the
stature of the fullness of Christ’ and so become fully human (Eph. 4.13:
andra teleion). There could be no fully human relationships if love was
the prerogative of husbands alone.
Husbands
are to love their wives; but wives too share in the calling of God to be ‘holy
and blameless before him in love’ (1.4) — a love that includes the husband.
This love is what is intended in the exhortation to be subject. Despite the
appearance of a
unilateral
subjection, Christian subjection is reciprocal (5.21), and reciprocal
subjection is nothing other than reciprocal love. The exhortation to wives to
be subject to their husbands and to husbands to love their wives constitutes a single
exhortation to mutual subjection or love. That at least is its substance,
behind the facade of an order in which one is still (nominally) above and the
other below.
...
so that he might sanctify it, having made it clean by the washing of water, in
the word, so that he might present the church to himself in glory, having no
stain or wrinkle or any such thing, so that it might be holy and blameless. (vv. 26±7) At the
beginning of v. 26, the feminine pronoun auten might be translated
either ‘it’ or ‘her’. (In the phrase translated, ‘making it clean . . .
’, there is no pronoun in the Greek.) If gender is projected from the
husband±wife relationship onto the Christ±church relationship, then the
maleness that is everywhere a background attribute of Christ is here brought
into the foreground as the church is feminized. This also affects the
translation of v. 25, where a feminine pronoun again refers to the church: did
Christ give himself up ‘for it’ or ‘for her’ (huper autes)? In v. 27,
similarly, the phrase ‘so that it might be ... ’ could also be rendered
‘so that she might be ... ’ Thus RSV translates the relevant passage: ‘.
. . and gave himself up for her, that he might sanctify her,
having cleansed her by the washing of water with the word, that he might
present the church to himself in splendour, without spot or wrinkle or any such
thing, that she might be holy and without blemish’ (compare NRSV, NIV,
JB). The church here is clearly the bride of Christ, prepared for her wedding
by her future husband. The passage is then reminiscent of the prophetic image
of Yahweh and Israel as husband and wife, and especially of Ezekiel 16.9, where
Yahweh reminds his wife (here, Jerusalem) how ‘I bathed you with water [elousa
se en hudati] and washed [apepluna] your blood from you, and
anointed you with oil’. On the other hand, REB translates the passage: ‘. . .
and gave himself up for it, to consecrate and cleanse it by water
and word, so that he might present the church to himself all glorious, with no
stain or wrinkle or anything of the sort, but holy and without blemish’
(compare NEB, AV, RV). On this translation, there is no reference here to the
hgure of a ‘holy and spotless bride’ (von Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord,
vii.480).
The church is to be
‘without stain or wrinkle’, and the term rupis (‘wrinkle’) might seem to
favour the view that the church here is personihed and feminized. If the
reference is to a facial wrinkle, then the spilos might similarly
refer not to a ‘stain’ but to some kind of facial blemish. In that case, we
behold here the pure, clear complexion of the church; a feminine church, a
radiant bride prepared for her wedding day. But the imagery is not consistent.
Christ purihes the church ‘by the washing of water, in the word’ (that is, in
the baptism that follows the preaching of the word). Any ‘stains’ or ‘wrinkles’
that are removed are removed by washing in water; they are not facial
blemishes, as though Christ were presented here as a beautician or cosmetic
surgeon. The language appears to stop short of personihcation; there is no
clear reference to the face of Christ’s partner.
More importantly,
Paul has already indicated that the relation of Christ to the church is not
that of a husband to his wife but that of the head to the body. Christ is ‘the
head of the church’, and as such he is ‘saviour of the body’ (5.23); this
correlation between the head and the church as his body has also occurred
earlier in the letter (1.22—3, 4-I5—I6) and in Colossians
(Col. 1.18, 2.19). The head-body image is too hrmly established in this late
Pauline theology for it to be possible to sever the head from the body, as it
were, in order to reconstitute the body as a distinct person, Christ’s bride.
The husband is head of the wife ‘as’ Christ is head of the body, but the
analogy is set against the background of fundamental differences. In Ephesians
5.28—30 Paul attempts to make the analogy closer by comparing Christ’s relation
to the church to the husband’s relation to his own body, which then in
turn illustrates his relation to his wife. The stains and wrinkles that are
removed by washing are therefore the marks that must be removed if the church
is truly to be Christ’s body, growing up into its heavenly head. There is no
room here for a transcendent feminine other.[lxv]
‘The husband is head
of the wife as Christ is head of the church, and is himself saviour of the
body’ (v. 23). The point of similarity is confined to the relation indicated by
the term ‘head’. Otherwise the husband is unlike Christ. He is not head of the
church, he is not saviour of the body; he is certainly not saviour of his
wife’s body. She may acknowledge him as her head, but not as her saviour.
Husbands are to love their wives as Christ loved the church (v. 25), and here
the point of similarity is confined to the term ‘love’. Christ gave himself up
for the church; but the husband does not give himself up for his wife. Christ
sanctihes and washes the church, removing every impurity so that he may ®nally
be united with it in glory; but the husband performs no such service for his
wife. Far from being placed on a pedestal, the husband is helped down from the
pedestal on which he may perhaps be standing, so as to stand instead with his
feet on the ground, alongside his wife. In comparison with the exaltation of
Christ to be our true head, ‘far above every rule and authority and power and
lordship’ (1.21), the earthly pedestal looks ridiculous, and it is a relief to
be rid of it and to live the truly human life of mutual agape and subjection
rather than the imposing but inhuman life of the hgure of marble or stone. In
the new covenant, stony hearts are transformed into living human flesh (cf. Ez.
36.26, 2 Cor. 3.3).
THE HOMECOMING OF EROS [VERSES 28 ± 33)
Thus
husbands ought to love their wives as they do their own bodies. He who loves
his wife loves himself. For no one ever hates his own flesh but nourishes and
tends it, just as Christ does the church; for we are members of his body. (vv. 28-30) Man’s
love for his own body is a fleshly love, and to withhold this love - despising
the body, regarding it as a corpse to which one’s true self is chained - is to
be guilty of inhumanity and self-deception. The body stands in constant need of
shelter, clothing, food, drink, washing, exercise, relaxation and sleep. Being
fragile, it needs to be protected from all that endangers it. From time to
time, it will need medical attention (although one should accept with a good
grace that the time bestowed on it by God is finite and not unlimited). The
body is not to be pampered, but certain comforts are not to be denied it. The
dividing-line between what it needs for its survival and what it demands for
its comfort is not easy to draw, and to insist on this distinction - although
this is often perhaps a necessary corrective - may be to imply the existence of
a God other than the creator-God who ‘gives generously and without reproach to
all’ (Jas. 1.5). It is human to love the human body because it is divine to
love the human body, and because an alleged divinity that despises the human
body and urges the human spirit to do likewise is a false god projected by
human self-alienation. Of course, the despairing cry, ‘Who will deliver me from
this body of death?’ has its own rationale and justification. Human
self-alienation is real. Yet this cry is immediately followed by a
thanksgiving — ‘Thanks be to God through Jesus Christ our Lord!’ — which arises
from the knowledge that the body is not simply the place of death but that,
through participation in the death and resurrection of Jesus’ body, it finds
again its own original life. The resurrection is the recovery of the natural,
created life of the body — its securing in the face of all that threatens it.
But in
Ephesians 5 the ‘natural’ love of the fleshly body is invoked in support of the
exhortation to husbands to love their wives. It is as unnatural for a husband
not to love his wife as it is for him not to love his own body. Since she is a
being of flesh and blood as he is, his love for her is a fleshly love. Her
flesh — the flesh created by God and declared to be good, not ‘the flesh’ in
its parasitic fallen form — will be the object of his care and attentiveness
just as his own flesh is; or rather, she herself in her fleshliness will be the
object of his care and attentiveness. This relation is reciprocal, yet the
emphasis is placed here not on this reciprocity but on the particular calling
of the husband to cherish and tend his wife’s flesh as his own — thus
fulfilling the commandment to love his neighbour as himself. Within marriage,
it seems, agape takes a peculiarly fleshly form. Human fleshliness is another
constant factor of human existence which, in any given interaction with
another, may stand closer to the background or to the foreground. (In the
background during a telephone conversation, it is in the foreground during a
medical consultation about a health problem.) Marriage is a mode of human
interrelation in which the whole person stands in the foreground, including its
fleshly aspect. In marriage, man and woman eat, drink, wash, dress, exercise,
relax and sleep together, and these are all the affairs of the body. The
body of the one is constantly present to the other, in the micro-events of
daily life but also in the passage of the years, in which bodily life together
moves through its various stages towards its eventual limit. The intimacy of
husband and wife differs from other forms of intimacy in the extent to which it
is a physical, bodily intimacy. Although agape is never purely bodily, any more
than it is ever purely disembodied, it here reveals a marked bias towards the
flesh. And, somewhere within this bodily intimacy, hidden yet manifestly
permeating the entire relationship, is the factor of eros. If eros must elsewhere
be limited in order to preserve the space of agape, at this point eros is to be
found within the space of agape.
Eros is
not the whole, and it would be meaningless to describe it as the most important
element in the fleshly agape of marriage, or as at its centre. But it has its
own unique importance. It is often said that eros is not only a means to an
end (i.e. procreation) but also an end in itself, intrinsically good.15 But
15 Barth finds this point illustrated by
Gen. 2, where 'the reference is to man and woman in their relationship as such,
and therefore not to fatherhood and mother- that is to divide something
that is a single though complex phenomenon. Within marriage, there are not two
sexual acts, one that intends procreation and another that intends only itself,
in its intrinsic goodness. Where this distinction is made, the tendency is to
regard ‘procreation’ as a predominantly biological phenomenon, a non-obligatory
supplement to a sexual act whose intrinsic goodness lies in its capacity to spiritualize
the flesh. In the ‘household code’ of Ephesians, however, there is no
disjunction between the relation of husband and wife and the relation of parent
and child (however limited the Pauline treatment of this latter relation may
be). Rather than accepting a duality of mutuality and procreation, it is
preferable to suppose that there is within marriage a single sexual act
whose mutuality is intrinsic to it as the precondition of the procreation
that the act intends. From a biological point of view, it is clear enough
that the act intends procreation. But this ‘biological point of view’ is no
more than a single strand within the complex, living continuum in which a third
party comes into being and begins to participate in the shared bodily intimacy
of those it will learn to address as its ‘mother’ and ‘father’. Procreation is
primarily a social event, and only as such is it also a biological event. But
sexual union is also a social event, and it is as the social
precondition for procreation that it is also its biological precondition. The
immediate, ‘normal’, normative social context of the begetting, conceiving,
bearing and rearing of children is the relation of physical intimacy between
man and woman within which there is the special physical intimacy of sexual
union.
Why, apart from
biological considerations, is this particular act a necessary precondition of
the physical intimacy into which there may enter a third, a fourth, a fifth . .
. ? Husbands, we recall, are to love their wives ‘as their own bodies’ (Eph.
5.28). In marriage, agape takes a peculiarly fleshly form, disclosing
hood or the establishment of the
family. . . The relationship of man and woman has its own reality and dignity’ (CD
111/2, 293; compare CD iii/i,
312 — 15). But the eroticism of Gen. 2.23—5 and the call to procreation of Gen.
1.28 should not be separated from one another. In the exegesis of Gen. 1 — 2
that occupies most of CD iii/i,
the sharp distinction between the ‘P’ and ‘J’ creation accounts means that
connections are sometimes overlooked. here a bias towards the
physical intimacy of bodily proximity. The bodies of husband and wife are near
one another and constantly present to one another. Yet in cohabiting, eating,
sleeping or ageing together, considered in themselves, they remain two. The
body of the other is in close proximity to one's own body, but it is not as
one's own body. The body continues to occupy its own space and its boundary
remains intact, even where the two bodies establish physical contact with one
another through touch. It is true that all physical intimacy involves a single,
shared space. But that shared space (or shared space-time) is the external
space within which the body exists, in proximity to the other; it is the
social and physical space that contains one's own body and the body of
the other. There is, so far, no sharing of the space of the body itself
± the internal space marked out and enclosed by the boundary between body and
world. Physical proximity to the other does not in itself cross this boundary.
That crossing of the boundary into the bodily space of the other, at the same
time an admission of the other into one's own bodily space, is what occurs in
sexual union. In sexual union, the body continues to occupy its own space, but
it does not do so alone. Its own space is now also the space of an other, a
shared space. This shared space is a shared physical space, but it cannot be
reduced to this any more than it can be reduced to a purely biological
phenomenon. My body is (secondarily) a biological phenomenon and its space is
a physical space, but it is in the ®rst instance the possibility and the locus
of my own life as lived among others. The mutual crossing of the bodily
boundary is the social event that completes or ‘consummates' the bodily
intimacy of marriage, establishing the peculiar nature of marriage as that
social relationship in which even the internal space of the body itself is not
withheld. It is not the telos of that bodily intimacy; one does not
live, eat, sleep with another for the sake of sexual union. It is more
like the keystone of an arch, or the ®nal piece in a jigsaw puzzle, without
which the whole would be dehcient, although once it is in place it need not
continue to draw special attention to itself but exists only within a larger
whole. Human arbitrariness or inventiveness can ®nd new uses for the act of
sexual union; the keystone of an arch or a piece of a jigsaw puzzle can no
doubt be set within very different structures. But these will not be their
natural habitat. And the natural habitat of sexual union is the physical
intimacy of marriage, which it completes in the mutual opening-up even of the
previously enclosed space of the body itself.
If the original and
normative context for sexual union is marriage, then the original and normative
context for eros is agape. Marriage is not necessarily characterized by agape.
It is said to the woman that, in marriage outside paradise, ‘Your desire shall
be for your husband and he shall rule over you’ (Gen. 3.16): the imbalance here
between her desire and his rule suggests a disruption and distortion of the
original goodness of the co-humanity of male and female. Agape is the proper telos
of marriage, but it is disclosed as such only in Christ, the embodiment of the
divine-human agape. Apart from this disclosure, how clear would it be that
agape is the telos of marriage? The assumption that ‘love’ (or ‘romantic
love’) is the primary basis for marriage is often said to be an innovation of
the modern West. It is certainly a central preoccupation of the novel,
the literary genre most characteristic of the modern West. The novel holds up a
mirror to what is held to be the reality of ‘love and marriage’; it is the
image of a representation that arises from the reality and exercises an
influence over it, although the reality is never reducible to the
representation.[lxvi] In the image of the novel, certain conventional
assumptions about love become visible. One character ‘falls in love’ with
another, and this is equivalent to his wanting to marry her. If she announces
that she ‘cannot love him’, this is equivalent to a refusal of
marriage. Outside the sphere of the modern West, the assumption that this love
is the indispensable and sufficient condition for marriage is, perhaps, much
less ‘natural’. But in the present context the more important question is how
this modern western ‘love’ is related to agape. Even in the traditional novel,
the link between love and marriage is in fact contingent. Marriage is often an
end (the end of the novel), and not a transition to a new beginning. If
marriage is the goal of love but not the context of its continuing
development, is marriage tacitly presented as the end of love? Where, at
the beginning of the novel, marriage has already occurred, love may well be
sought outside marriage; the rendering of a love that both issues in marriage
and develops and matures within it is much less usual (in spite of Anna
Karenina, where this theme is rendered in counterpoint with the more
traditional theme of extra-marital love). The more recent convention that
‘love’ is the precondition not of marriage but of ‘sex’ is a natural
development of tradition rather than a reaction against it. ‘Modern’ and
‘traditional’ novels tend to display an ambivalence towards marriage combined
with an unshaken faith in ‘love’ itself. (Where this faith in love is withheld,
leaving behind only a loveless ‘sex’, the novel will be self-consciously
cynical in tone.) These novels are familiar with the assumption that marriage
is the proper context and home of love, but, in declining to make this
assumption narratively plausible, their tendency is to induce scepticism
towards it. They thereby hold up a mirror to the combination of faith in ‘love’
and ambivalence towards marriage that characterizes the representation of
reality in discourse. If ‘love’ is seen as the blending of agape (a commitment
to the whole person?) and eros (sexual attraction), then marriage is not its
natural context or home in practice, even if it ought to be in theory; or so we
are led to suspect, both by the novel and by the ‘experience’ that it reflects
and shapes. If the novel holds up a true image, the modern West is the place
where it is assumed both that love is the precondition and foundation of
marriage and that this assumption is questionable or untrue. In this context,
the claim that marriage is the home of a love that reflects the relationship of
Christ and the church appears to belong only to the ethos of idealization,
fragile aspiration and half-truth that pervades a wedding service. Only rarely
does a novel (or the discourse that it reflects) show any knowledge of the
divine-human agape that is the foundation of all things or of the possibility
that marriage might be an expression of this reality.
The original and
normative context for sexual union is marriage, just as the original and
normative context for eros is agape: this is not a self-evident truth but a
distinctively Christian insight (whatever analogies there may be elsewhere).
It follows that extra-marital sexual relationships that claim to be based in
‘love’ are not in fact a true expression of agape. Agape is in the first
instance ‘the love of Christ’. In Ephesians 3.18—19, to ‘know the love of
Christ that surpasses knowledge’ is equivalent to comprehending ‘what is the
breadth and length and height and depth’. The breadth and length and height and
depth of the love of Christ surpass knowledge, but they may nevertheless be
imperfectly but really known. They are known not by detached observers but by those
whose entire lives are ‘rooted and grounded in love’ (this love, the
love of Christ). The breadth of the love of Christ lies in its embrace not only
of those who are near but also of those who are far off (2.17). There is no
spatial limitation to the love of Christ on the horizontal plane. The length of
the love of Christ is seen in the absence of temporal limitation. The love of
Christ precedes the beginning — before the foundation of the world we were
chosen in the beloved and for love (1.4—6) — and it outlasts the end, enduring
for ever. The height and depth of the love of Christ indicate the absence of
any vertical limit. We are not referred simply to an earthly event that would
leave space for quite different events elsewhere, but to an event that expresses
the divine plan ‘to unite all things in Christ, things in heaven and things on
earth’ (1.10). The love of Christ is not marked off by any external limit. Is
there an internal limit, set by the body of the beloved? But this body
is Christ’s own body; he is its head. The body cannot live without the head,
nor can the head live without the body: to sever the head from the body is to
destroy both head and body. Head and body occupy their own space, but they also
share a single space. Just as there is no external limit to the love of Christ,
whether spatial or temporal, so there is no internal limit.
Head and
body are one. A man’s care for his own body is an image of Christ’s love for
the church (5.29—30); but this image is merely a transition to the image of the
love of Christ that is found in the love of man and woman.
If there is to be an
inner-human image of the love of Christ within the eros of man and woman, there
must be a counterpart here to the absence of limit. The agape of marriage must
be marked by the absence of a spatial limit. Physical proximity is the
norm here, but this agape is not destroyed by temporary physical separation.
Separation is not to be seen as a welcome opportunity to behave for a while as
though this agape did not exist. Nor is there any temporal limit to this
agape, other than the limit of human existence itself. This agape is not a
short-term or renewable contract, and divorce is fundamentally alien to it. To
this absence of an external limit, spatial or temporal, there corresponds
an absence of internal limit. The boundary that encloses the space of
the body itself is no longer sacrosanct, but dissolves into the shared space of
two bodies become one flesh. Agape here occupies the territory of eros.
'For
that reason a man shall leave his father and mother and shall be joined to his
wife, and the two shall become one flesh.' This is a great mystery; I speak of
Christ and the church. However that may be, let each of you love his own wife
as himself, and let the wife respect her husband. (vv. 31—3) The scriptural text
(Gen. 2.24) speaks of marriage — not in the distorted forms it takes after the
fall (Gen. 3.16) but in the original, created form that still subsists beneath
the distortions and that becomes visible again when the existing institution of
marriage is exposed to the light of Christ. ‘When anything is exposed by the
light it becomes visible, for anything that becomes visible is light. Therefore
it is said: Awake, O sleeper, and arise from the dead, and Christ shall give
you light’ (Eph. 5.13—14). The daylight that Christ brings dispels the dreams
and nightmares of the dark and discloses the world as it truly is. His
disclosure of the original nature of marriage makes it possible for marriage,
the relation of man and woman as husband and wife, to bear witness to him in
his relation to the church. As we reflect on the nature of this
belonging-together of man and woman, we are also compelled to speak of the love
of Christ for the church; and as we set these realities alongside one another,
allowing the greater to illumine the lesser but also the lesser to illumine the
greater, we learn to know the love of Christ and the love of man and woman in
new and unforeseen ways. Rooted and grounded in the love of Christ for the ekklesia,
the love of man and woman becomes an acted parable of that love, and in
pointing to the love that is its own comprehensive context it also uncovers its
own true meaning. Thus it can be said of the love of man and woman as
originally created by God: ‘This is a great mystery.’ Sacramentum hoc magnum
est. It is not that this fleshly, material reality becomes transparent to a
higher, spiritual reality, losing its own proper being in the process. There is
no sacrifice here of the letter to the spirit. The correspondence of the lesser
love to the greater love confirms and establishes the lesser love in setting it
within its proper context, which is the mystery of God’s will, his plan for the
fullness of the times to gather up and reconcile all things in Christ (1.9—10).
If this plan is a
reality, then we should expect to see correspondences, partial, frail, yet
actual, between earthly phenomena (the phaneroumena illumined by the
divine light (5.14)) and the peace and love of Christ. These phenomena will
then become parables. Jesus’ own parables are ‘the prototype of the
order in which there can be other true words alongside the one Word of God,
created and determined by it, exactly corresponding to it, fully serving it
and therefore enjoying its power and authority’ (Barth, CD iv/3, 113).[lxvii] As Jesus utters his parables, ‘the material is
everywhere transformed, and there is an equation of the kingdom with them, and
of them with the kingdom, in which the being, words and activities of
labourers, slave-owners, kings, fathers, sons, etc., become real testimony to
the real presence of God on earth, and therefore to the events of this real
presence’ (113). Labourers, fathers, sons, yet not only men but also women:
women bread-making or searching for a lost coin, bridesmaids awaiting the
arrival of the bridegroom. If women as well as men inhabit these stories, the
original belonging-together of man and woman might itself become a parable. Eve
is present to Adam and Adam to Eve, for the first time, in unashamed nakedness;
and this fleshly belonging- together finally dispels the possibility of a
solitary male existence that the Creator himself has declared to be ‘not good’
(Gen. 2.18). This parable is acted out whenever ‘a man leaves his father and
his mother and is joined to his wife, and the two become one flesh’. But that
common occurrence is not yet the meaning of the scriptural parable; in it, the
parable becomes an acted parable, and the meaning of this acted parable
is ‘Christ and the church’. The correspondence between parable and meaning is
anything but arbitrary, for both of them have their place within the single
divine oikonomia (Eph. 1.10, 3.9). ‘The order of reconciliation’ is also
‘the confirmation and restoration of the order of creation’, and within it ‘the
eternal meaning and content of the order of creation is worked out in the one
order of God . . .’ (CD, iv/3, 43). It is perhaps not appropriate to
describe the belonging-together of man and woman in agape and eros as the ®rst
or the greatest of the parables, but it must still be said: sacramentum hoc
magnum est.
The parable is a
mystery, and the divine oikonomia is a mystery of reconciliation.
The cruci®ed Christ reaches out to embrace Gentiles, formerly at enmity with
the people of Israel but now a holy temple built upon the foundation of the
Jewish apostles and prophets (Eph. 2.11-22). In Christ, the two become one as
the enmity is dispelled (2.14). Is this also true of man and woman? ‘No man
hates his own flesh’ (5.29); but it is unfortunately possible for a man to
hate his own wife, and he must therefore repeatedly be exhorted to love her
(5.25 - 33). It is also possible for a woman to despise her husband, and she is
therefore exhorted to respect him (5.33). There is every possibility that this
relationship of physical intimacy will degenerate into a vicious circle of
hatred and contempt, within which age- old stereotypes and postures that divide
man and woman will once again come to expression. Children too may be drawn
into this abyss. They are subject to the divine command, ‘Honour your father
and mother’, and to the promise of wellbeing that accompanies it (6.2—3). But
how are they to honour a father who dishonours their mother, or a mother who
dishonours their father? For them, there is no inclusive parental agape to
serve as an earthly image of the love of Christ that surpasses knowledge.
Where, on the other hand, there is mutual love and mutual subjection, the oikonomia
of the home may become for them an image of the oikonomia of God. Within
this parental order, there is an explicit ‘instruction and discipline of the
Lord’ (6.4); but the inclusive agape of husband and wife also has its part to
play in handing down to the next generation the knowledge of the divine agape
embodied in Jesus. Where there is this agape, it may be said: ‘He is our peace,
who has made the two one, breaking down the dividing-wall of enmity in his
flesh’ (2.14)..
This reconciliation
of man and woman is also the reconciliation of agape and eros. Within the
corporate life of the ekklesia, the symbol of the veil marks a boundary
that eros is not to transgress if agape is to be preserved. Forcibly separated
from agape, eros is left out in the cold. We should not feel too sorry for him,
however, for his exclusion is the result of his own shameless attempt to
recreate the human person in his own image — not from without but from within,
in the sinister form of concupiscentia, the law of sin that dwells
within me. Like Milton’s Satan, eros cannot bear to be merely a creature. He
must be divine and wield a divine creative power. Yet as the eroticized human
person is a distortion rather than a genuinely new creation, so this divinized
eros is a distortion of a creaturely reality which continues to participate in
the original divine affirmation. In the beginning, God saw everything that he
had made, culminating in the human creature in its twofold existence as male
and female — and behold, it was very good. In the agape of man and woman, eros
sheds his pretensions, like the prodigal son in the far country, and returns
home.